1 / 66

In Defense of Physicalist Accounts of Consciousness

This paper explores the possibility of scientific accounts of consciousness from a physicalist perspective, refuting influential arguments against it. It argues that a better understanding of science can shed light on the feasibility of such accounts.

abradshaw
Download Presentation

In Defense of Physicalist Accounts of Consciousness

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. In Defense of Physicalist Accounts of Consciousness Ron Chrisley School of Cognitive & Computing Sciences, University of Sussex After October 1st: School of Computer Science, University of Birmingham Toward A Science of Consciousness 2001 Skövde, Sweden August 11, 2001 TSC 2001

  2. Can we have ascienceofconsciousness? TSC 2001

  3. Can we have ascienceofconsciousness? TSC 2001

  4. Ö Can we have ascienceofconsciousness? TSC 2001

  5. More specifically:Can we have aphysicalistscienceof consciousness? TSC 2001

  6. Take-Home Message If we gain a better understanding of what science is, then we will have a better idea of whether particular scientific accounts of consciousness are possible I’ll show this by looking at particular case – even if you disagree with the details, you can still agree with the general point TSC 2001

  7. Overview • Look at three influential arguments against the possibility of a physicalist account of consciousness: TSC 2001

  8. Overview • Look at three influential arguments against the possibility of a physicalist account of consciousness: • Nagel: incompatibility of subjective and objective TSC 2001

  9. Overview • Look at three influential arguments against the possibility of a physicalist account of consciousness: • Nagel: incompatibility of subjective and objective • Jackson: knowledge argument (feat. Mary) TSC 2001

  10. Overview • Look at three influential arguments against the possibility of a physicalist account of consciousness: • Nagel: incompatibility of subjective and objective • Jackson: knowledge argument (feat. Mary) • Chalmers: lack of logical supervenience (zombie earth) TSC 2001

  11. Overview • Show that these arguments only work on a particular and implausible view of science: TSC 2001

  12. Overview • Show that these arguments only work on a particular and implausible view of science: • Objectivity as “the view from nowhere” TSC 2001

  13. Overview • Show that these arguments only work on a particular and implausible view of science: • Objectivity as “the view from nowhere” • Science as non-experiential TSC 2001

  14. Overview • Show that these arguments only work on a particular and implausible view of science: • Objectivity as “the view from nowhere” • Science as non-experiential • Explanations as logical deductions TSC 2001

  15. Strategy/Caveats Will argue for the possibility of physicalist accounts of consciousness: TSC 2001

  16. Strategy/Caveats Will argue for the possibility of physicalist accounts of consciousness: • By refuting three influential arguments against same TSC 2001

  17. Strategy/Caveats Will argue for the possibility of physicalist accounts of consciousness: • By refuting three influential arguments against same • Not a direct argument; failure of the three arguments is compatible with the impossibility of physicalist accounts TSC 2001

  18. Strategy/Caveats Will argue for the possibility of physicalist accounts of consciousness: • By refuting three influential arguments against same • Not a direct argument; failure of the three arguments is compatible with the impossibility of physicalist accounts • Will be brisk, leaving out detail, and assuming familiarity with the three arguments to be rejected TSC 2001

  19. Defining terms • “Physicalist” TSC 2001

  20. Defining terms • “Physicalist” • Non-dualistic, ontologically conservative TSC 2001

  21. Defining terms • “Physicalist” • Non-dualistic, ontologically conservative • Roughly: business as usual TSC 2001

  22. Defining terms • “Physicalist” • Non-dualistic, ontologically conservative • Roughly: business as usual • “Account” TSC 2001

  23. Defining terms • “Physicalist” • Non-dualistic, ontologically conservative • Roughly: business as usual • “Account” • Scientific TSC 2001

  24. Defining terms • “Physicalist” • Non-dualistic, ontologically conservative • Roughly: business as usual • “Account” • Scientific • Where the action is TSC 2001

  25. Defining terms • “Physicalist” • Non-dualistic, ontologically conservative • Roughly: business as usual • “Account” • Scientific • Where the action is • “Consciousness” TSC 2001

  26. Defining terms • “Physicalist” • Non-dualistic, ontologically conservative • Roughly: business as usual • “Account” • Scientific • Where the action is • “Consciousness” • Phenomenal awareness: “hard problem” TSC 2001

  27. Nagel’s argument:Subjectivity vs objectivity • Consciousness is a subjective phenomenon TSC 2001

  28. Nagel’s argument:Subjectivity vs objectivity • Consciousness is a subjective phenomenon • That is, consciousness is accessible only from a subjective point of view TSC 2001

  29. Nagel’s argument:Subjectivity vs objectivity • Consciousness is a subjective phenomenon • That is, consciousness is accessible only from a subjective point of view • But scientific accounts should be objective TSC 2001

  30. Nagel’s argument:Subjectivity vs objectivity • Consciousness is a subjective phenomenon • That is, consciousness is accessible only from a subjective point of view • But scientific accounts should be objective • Objective accounts are from “no point of view”, or a “God’s-eye view”: contain no subjectivity TSC 2001

  31. Nagel’s argument:Subjectivity vs objectivity • Consciousness is a subjective phenomenon • That is, consciousness is accessible only from a subjective point of view • But scientific accounts should be objective • Objective accounts are from “no point of view”, or a “God’s-eye view”: contain no subjectivity • Thus, science cannot explain subjective consciousness TSC 2001

  32. Rejecting “The view from nowhere” • Nagel’s mistake concerns the nature of objectivity TSC 2001

  33. Rejecting “The view from nowhere” • Nagel’s mistake concerns the nature of objectivity • Not a God’s eye view, not a “perspectiveless perspective” TSC 2001

  34. Rejecting “The view from nowhere” • Nagel’s mistake concerns the nature of objectivity • Not a God’s eye view, not a “perspectiveless perspective” • Rather, a way of negotiating human, perspective-bound views; “a view from anywhere” (Brian Cantwell Smith, On the Origin of Objects) TSC 2001

  35. Rejecting “The view from nowhere” • Nagel’s mistake concerns the nature of objectivity • Not a God’s eye view, not a “perspectiveless perspective” • Rather, a way of negotiating human, perspective-bound views; “a view from anywhere” (Brian Cantwell Smith, On the Origin of Objects) • Thus, no incompatibility between objectivity and subjective experience TSC 2001

  36. Jackson’s knowledge argument • Suppose there is a scientist, Mary, who has all the physical information about vision, but has never actually seen colour. TSC 2001

  37. Jackson’s knowledge argument • Suppose there is a scientist, Mary, who has all the physical information about vision, but has never actually seen colour. • When she eventually does see, say, red, she learns something she didn’t know before: what it’s like to see red TSC 2001

  38. Jackson’s knowledge argument • Suppose there is a scientist, Mary, who has all the physical information about vision, but has never actually seen colour. • When she eventually does see, say, red, she learns something she didn’t know before: what it’s like to see red • So physical information is not all the information about consciousness TSC 2001

  39. Rejecting the non-experiential view of science • Jackson’s mistake is to assume that science is a set of propositions that can be written down and read, independently of experience TSC 2001

  40. Rejecting the non-experiential view of science • Jackson’s mistake is to assume that science is a set of propositions that can be written down and read, independently of experience • Rather, science is an experiential activity, not just the “output” of that activity TSC 2001

  41. Rejecting the non-experiential view of science • Jackson’s mistake is to assume that science is a set of propositions that can be written down and read, independently of experience • Rather, science is an experiential activity, not just the “output” of that activity • To be sure, text plays a big role in the activity of science, but so also does experience TSC 2001

  42. Rejecting the non-experiential view of science • Jackson’s mistake is to assume that science is a set of propositions that can be written down and read, independently of experience • Rather, science is an experiential activity, not just the “output” of that activity • To be sure, text plays a big role in the activity of science, but so also does experience • Science does not aspire to provide an account of anything to anyone independently of their experience TSC 2001

  43. What to do about Mary? • Mary may have all the “physical information”, but does not know everything that science knows about vision TSC 2001

  44. What to do about Mary? • Mary may have all the “physical information”, but does not know everything that science knows about vision • Thus, the fact that she learns something does not indicate some limitation of science TSC 2001

  45. What to do about Mary? • Mary may have all the “physical information”, but does not know everything that science knows about vision • Thus, the fact that she learns something does not indicate some limitation of science • Science presupposes that one already knows what is trying to be explained TSC 2001

  46. What to do about Mary? • Mary may have all the “physical information”, but does not know everything that science knows about vision • Thus, the fact that she learns something does not indicate some limitation of science • Science presupposes that one already knows what is trying to be explained • It does not atempt to make this intelligible for those for whom the problem does not arise TSC 2001

  47. Chalmers’ argument:the possibility of Zombie Earth • Scientific explanations must show how the lower-level facts logically entail what is to be explained TSC 2001

  48. Chalmers’ argument:the possibility of Zombie Earth • Scientific explanations must show how the lower-level facts logically entail what is to be explained • We can imagine a Zombie Earth, physically identical to Earth, but with no consciousness at all TSC 2001

  49. Chalmers’ argument:the possibility of Zombie Earth • Scientific explanations must show how the lower-level facts logically entail what is to be explained • We can imagine a Zombie Earth, physically identical to Earth, but with no consciousness at all • So consciousness is not logically entailed by physical facts TSC 2001

  50. Chalmers’ argument:the possibility of Zombie Earth • Scientific explanations must show how the lower-level facts logically entail what is to be explained • We can imagine a Zombie Earth, physically identical to Earth, but with no consciousness at all • So consciousness is not logically entailed by physical facts • So there cannot be a physicalist explanation of consciousness TSC 2001

More Related