1 / 64

Pascal’s wager

Pascal’s wager. Simplified version: “It’s safer to be a believer than a nonbeliever. As a believer, if you’re right you go to heaven and if you’re wrong it’s no big deal. But as a nonbeliever, if you’re right it’s no big deal and if you’re wrong you go to hell” Why believe in God?

asoluri
Download Presentation

Pascal’s wager

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. Pascal’s wager • Simplified version: • “It’s safer to be a believer than a nonbeliever. As a believer, if you’re right you go to heaven and if you’re wrong it’s no big deal. But as a nonbeliever, if you’re right it’s no big deal and if you’re wrong you go to hell” • Why believe in God? • ‘epistemic reasons’: reasons that concern what’s most plausible, likely to be true, backed by evidence, intellectually justified, etc. • e.g., the design argument • ‘prudential reasons’: reasons that concern what’s in your own best interest, what’s to your advantage, what makes your (after)life go better, etc. • e.g., Pascal’s wager

  2. Pascal in the Pensées • Reason • “Reason can decide nothing here” • Pascal thinks it’s intellectually unclear whether God exists: “I look on all sides, and I see only darkness everywhere. Nature presents to me nothing which is not matter of doubt and concern.” • He mentions the “Deus absconditus” (hidden God) of Scripture (Isaiah 45:15, Vulgate). • This is supposed to be part of Christianity: “[Christians] profess a religion for which they cannot give a reason”, “[Christianity] says that men are in darkness and estranged from God, that He has hidden Himself from their knowledge”

  3. Pascal in the Pensées • Intellectual integrity • “[A]ccording to reason, you can defend neither of the propositions”—neither theism nor atheism. • So, you might think, it’s therefore inappropriate to take a position: the best response to withhold judgment on the question. • That is, if there’s no intellectual basis for theism and none for atheism, then the most intellectually honest position is a kind of agnosticism. • But Pascal insists that “you must wager” and that “[i]t is not optional”—you have to take a position on this issue. • So there’s nothing intellectually dishonest in taking a position. You’re forced into it.

  4. Pascal in the Pensées • Wagering setup • You can either go with theism or atheism. • You have two things at stake: your reason and your will. • You might gain knowledge or you might fall into error. • You might gain happiness or you might fall into misery. • Wagering: reason • Since this is an intellectually unclear and forced choice, neither option will compromise the integrity of your reason. • Wagering: happiness • Go with theism: “If you gain, you gain all; if you lose, you lose nothing”

  5. Standard payoff matrix Heaven, hell, nothing lost or gained in this world

  6. ‘No hell’ payoff matrix Heaven, no hell, nothing lost or gained in this world

  7. Pascal in the Pensées • Cost of religious obedience • Pascal seems to start out with the assumption that there’s no cost to believing if God doesn’t exist (“if you lose, you lose nothing”) • But later he seems to allow for the view that there is a real cost, in giving up a happy life (“I may perhaps wager too much”). • In any case, since “what you stake is finite”, therefore the ‘wager’ still works.

  8. ‘Cost of obedience’ payoff matrix Heaven, hell, n = the cost in this world of religious obedience

  9. Pascal in the Pensées • Probabilities • Pascal seems to start with the assumption that God’s existence has a probability of 0.5 (“Since there is an equal risk of gain and of loss...”) • But he later allows for the view that the odds are against God’s existence, insisting that the ‘wager’ still works. • Just as [0.5(∞) + 0.5(-n)] > [0.5(-∞) + 0.5(0)], so too [0.01(∞) + 0.99(-n)] > [0.01(-∞) + 0.99(0)] • The wager still works, so long as God’s existence has a probability greater than zero, and so long as the cost of religious obedience in this world is finite.

  10. Pascal in the Pensées • Objection: choosing beliefs? • Pascal’s entire argument seems to rest on the assumption that beliefs can be voluntarily chosen (this view is called ‘doxastic voluntarism’). • But that assumption seems false. • My current belief is that cats do not lay eggs. I cannot simply choose to believe otherwise. • I can raise my arm at will, but I can’t change my beliefs at will. • So someone might object to Pascal, “Yes, I’m convinced that it’s to my advantage to be a believer, but I have no control over my beliefs!”

  11. Pascal in the Pensées • Reply: indirect control • Since your reason is not keeping you from belief, it must be your passions. • So don’t bother looking at proofs and reasoning; instead, work on your passions. • Imitate believers you know: “Follow the way by which they began; by acting as if they believed, taking the holy water, having masses said, etc.” • Eventually it will influence your passions and make you into a genuine believer. • In other words, even if we have no direct control over our beliefs, we still have indirect control.

  12. Summary • Reason can decide nothing. • You have to pick one side or the other. • You stand to gain more happiness by being a believer than by being a disbeliever. • This holds true even if there is a worldly cost to being a believer, and even if God’s existence is unlikely. • Even if you can’t directly choose to be a believer, you can gradually gain belief by imitating believers.

  13. Objections:intellectual honesty / personal integrity • Mackie on indirect control • Remember that Pascal says that picking a side will not compromise (or “shock”) your reason. • But Mackie thinks the indirect conversion process recommended by Pascal does just that. • He writes that, “in deliberately cultivating non-rational belief, one would be suppressing one’s critical faculties”—and Pascal himself writes that the process “will naturally make you believe, and deaden your acuteness”. • This is an especially big problem if you think the odds are against God’s existence—now Pascal’s recommendations are to “deliberately... reject all rational principles of belief in uncertainty”.

  14. Objections:intellectual honesty / personal integrity • Why not suspend judgment? • Remember that, despite his assumptions that reason doesn’t support theism or atheism, Pascal thinks it’s still okay to pick a side because you have to pick a side. • That is, he defends the intellectual integrity of picking a side by saying you can’t refuse to wager—this ‘suspension of judgment’ agnosticism isn’t a real alternative. • But why isn’t it a real alternative? • Maybe he thinks it’s not a legitimate alternative because such agnosticism is practically equivalent to atheism. • But even if that’s true, such agnosticism still seems intellectually superior to theism and atheism (at least given Pascal’s assumptions about what reason can tell us)

  15. Objections:intellectual honesty / personal integrity • Biting the bullet • Pascal might retreat to the claim that it is still rational to sacrifice one’s intellectual honesty and personal integrity. • After all, what’s a little dishonesty compared with eternal bliss? • A very principled nonbeliever might insist that it is never okay to sacrifice one’s integrity for the sake of self-interest. • But suppose you could get a trillion dollars just by getting yourself to form some trivial unjustified belief (e.g., that the trillionth digit of pi is odd)—wouldn’t that be okay? • Of course, Pascal spends a lot of time emphasizing the grave importance of the question of God’s existence. It therefore doesn’t seem like something to take trivially.

  16. Objections:intellectual honesty / personal integrity • Fooling God? • Mackie writes that Pascal needs God to be “both stupid enough and vain enough to be pleased with self-interested flattery” • Pascal could respond that, even if we find that kind of God distasteful, it’s still rational to be a believer in such a God. • A more palatable response: what starts out as self-interested flattery of God will eventually develop into genuine heartfelt worship of God. • That way, God might reward those who follow Pascal’s wager without being “stupid” or easily fooled.

  17. Objections:The ‘many gods’ objection • Pascal’s key assumption • Pascal seems to assume that there are only two possibilities: (1) God exists and rewards believers with heaven (and perhaps punishes nonbelievers with hell), and (2) God doesn’t exist and we’re all annihilated at death. • He even has a nonbeliever character say, “I know only that, in leaving this world, I fall for ever either into annihilation or into the hands of an angry God, without knowing to which of these two states I shall be for ever assigned.” • But this seems to overlook a lot of possibilities.

  18. Objections:The ‘many gods’ objection • Other possibilities • God exists, everyone goes to heaven. • God exists, everyone goes to hell. • God exists, only Protestant Christians go to heaven (everyone else goes to hell). • God exists, only Sunni Muslims go to heaven. • God exists, only people who speak Czech go to heaven. • God exists, believers go to hell, nonbelievers go to heaven. • God exists, everyone goes to heaven except those who follow Pascal’s wager—they go to hell.

  19. ‘Reversal’ payoff matrix Heaven, hell, n = the cost in this world of religious obedience

  20. Objections:The ‘many gods’ objection • Mackie on predestination • Perhaps “people are predestined to salvation or to non-salvation—perhaps to damnation—no matter what they now decide, or try to decide, to do” • If you think salvation is a matter of divine grace, and if you’re serious about avoiding Pelagianism, then you might think there’s nothing you personally can do to acquire salvation. • Pascal seems to make the controversial assumption that you personally can put a strategy into effect that will probably get you saved. • But if the Calvinist doctrine of double predestination is true, then that assumption cannot be made.

  21. Clifford’s “The Ethics of Belief” • Famous statement • “[I]t is wrong always, everywhere, and for any one, to believe anything upon insufficient evidence” • Famous shipwreck case • People die because some shipowner stifles his doubts about his ship’s seaworthiness. • Even if the ship didn’t sink, he’d still have had no right to believe on insufficient evidence. • Another case: public accusations • The charges turn out to be false, and the accusers are dishonored. • Even though they sincerely believed the charges were true, since they got their beliefs “by listening to the voice of prejudice and passion”, they had no right to believe.

  22. Belief and action • Objection • Their beliefs weren’t wrong, just their actions—they should have investigated more thoroughly before they acted. • Short reply • You can’t separate the belief from the action like this. After all, if you’ve already got strong beliefs on a matter, it’s impossible to do a fair and unbiased investigation.

  23. Longer reply • Beliefs are action-guiding • Beliefs by their very nature have an influence on actions. • Even a single trifling belief will have wider effects on other beliefs, as well as on our habits in accepting beliefs—eventually influencing our actions. • Beliefs are not private • “Our lives are guided” by the common opinions found throughout society. • We have a responsibility to take care of this stock of common opinion. • We owe it to the rest of humanity and to future generations to form our beliefs with evidence and testing.

  24. Longer reply • It’s everyone’s responsibility • This duty is not just for intellectuals. • Even the “rustic” and the “hard-worked wife” have an influence on the stock of common opinion—so they too are ‘on the hook’. • It’s not easy • Feeling like we know what’s going on gives us a pleasant sense of power. • And it feels bad to realize that we were wrong and lose this false sense of power. • But we have to give it up, out of respect for mankind.

  25. Longer reply • Character/habits: credulity • Unsupported belief is always bad, even when it doesn’t have the kind of bad effects you can point to. • For it weakens your intellectual habits, and makes you into a credulous person. • Cf. Even if stealing doesn’t hurt anyone, it makes the thief into a worse person. • We don’t want to end up with a society of credulous persons, “sink[ing] back into savagery” • Character/habits: dishonesty • If my mind is filled with unsupported beliefs, others are more willing to lie to me, and they get into bad habits. • Dishonesty spreads around alongside credulity, and we end up with a general disrespect for evidence and truth.

  26. Universal skepticism? • Objection • “Are we then to become universal sceptics, doubting everything, afraid always to put one foot before the other until we have personally tested the firmness of the road?” • Short reply • Certain matters concerning morality and the physical world have stood up to testing—they have a “practical certainty” • Also, you don’t need beliefs to act. It’s quite possible to act on probabilities—after all, that’s precisely how you get evidence.

  27. Longer reply: relying ontestimony and tradition • Testimony • It’s okay to accept testimony only when we have evidence that the reporter is honest, capable of knowing the matter, and reasonable. • In particular, it’s not enough for the report to be a good person. We need reason to think that he might know what he’s talking about. • Example: Even if Muhammad was a good person with excellent contributions to society, that doesn’t give Clifford any reason to trust his claims concerning the supernatural. • Example: Trusting a chemist is okay on normal matters of chemistry. But not if the chemist claims to know of an atom of oxygen existing throughout all time.

  28. Longer reply: relying ontestimony and tradition • Tradition • Tradition is good at “supply[ing] us with the means of asking questions, of testing and inquiring into things”—providing us with a framework for inquiry. • It shouldn’t be taken as “a collection of cut-and-dried statements to be accepted without further inquiry”. • We should accept the claims of tradition only when we have evidence that the persons responsible knew what they were talking about. • He illustrates this good use of tradition with examples from “the moral and... the material world”. • The “sacred tradition of humanity” consists in “questions rightly asked, in conceptions which enable us to ask further questions, and in methods of answering questions”.

  29. Conclusion • Moving beyond experience • Clifford also discusses what to think about “that which goes beyond our experience”. • The rule is to take our experience as a guide—we make the working assumption that nature is uniform. • Summing up • “We may believe what goes beyond our experience only when it is inferred from that experience by the assumption that what we do not know is like what we know” • “We may believe the statement of another person, when there is reasonable ground for supposing that he knows the matter of which he speaks, and that is speaking the truth as far as he knows it” • “It is wrong in all cases to believe on insufficient evidence; and where it is presumption to doubt and to investigate, there is more than presumption to believe”

  30. Objections to Clifford • Exaggerated consequences • Most commentators seem to agree that Clifford has overstated the bad consequences of beliefs based on insufficient evidence. • After all, perhaps people can hold to a limited class of such beliefs without losing all respect for evidence and all intellectual virtue. • e.g., some respected scientists claim to have religious convictions based on pure faith, backed by no evidence at all • And presumably lots of people can hold to wildly irrational beliefs without it having much of an influence on the rest of society. • Clifford could always insist that there’s something intrinsically wrong with unjustified beliefs, but then he’d be giving up his ‘destructive social consequences’ style of argument.

  31. Objections to Clifford • Foundational matters • It’s hard to know how to give evidence for things like the reliability of one’s senses, or the reliability of one’s memory, or the existence of an external world, etc. • Perhaps it’s okay to accept these things merely as working hypotheses, or to just take them for granted as a sort of background framework for thinking. • But then why can’t we take religious beliefs (like the existence of God) for granted in the same way? (Historically, a lot of people have done just that)

  32. Objections to Clifford • Foundational matters, cont’d • Maybe it’s okay to accept them because they’ve stood up to testing. • But the tests we use rely on things like the reliability of the senses, the existence of the external world, etc. They take for granted what we’re supposed to be testing for. • Similarly, the evidence we have for saying some testimony or some tradition is reliable and trustworthy is typically taken from previous testimony and tradition. • Generally, it’s hard to do tests or provide evidence without drawing on a large pre-existing stock of beliefs. • So, again, it’s unclear whether we need to have evidence for all our beliefs.

  33. Objections to Clifford • Children • How do we get beliefs in the first place? Are we supposed to rely on evidence from day one? • It seems implausible that a child would first need evidence of his mother’s reliability and trustworthiness before believing her claims about the names of things. • Perhaps the child should just take her claims as working assumptions for the purposes of further testing? • But if all you have to work with are working assumptions, how do you get the kind of evidence needed for justifying a belief?

  34. Objections to Clifford • Religious belief • Perhaps religious belief doesn’t fit Clifford’s rule because there’s no way to get evidence one way or the other. • Clifford would probably say that, even when evidence is unavailable, belief without evidence has bad consequences. • You might think that there are no bad consequences to religious beliefs like “God loves us and wants us to be nice”. • But Clifford would argue that these beliefs will in any case reinforce bad habits across the board. • So the heart of the matter might be this: Is it psychologically realistic that people can treat religious beliefs differently from their other beliefs, as a sort of isolated ‘special case’?

  35. William James’s“The Will to Believe” • James criticizes Clifford’s essay, arguing that belief on insufficient evidence is sometimes okay. • Distinctions, terminology: • Live / dead hypothesis: A hypothesis is dead when we couldn’t bring ourselves to believe it (e.g., the mythology of ancient Greece); otherwise it’s live. • Option: decision between two hypotheses • Living / dead option: between two live hypotheses? • Avoidable / forced option: possibility of not choosing? • Momentous / trivial: significant stake, irreversible decision?

  36. Psychology of human opinion • Against ‘doxastic voluntarism’ • We can’t change our beliefs at will. • A Pascal’s wager conversion would end up lacking “the inner soul of faith’s reality” • Without “some pre-existing tendency” towards Catholicism, imitating Catholics wouldn’t bring belief. • Non-intellectual influences • But beliefs aren’t entirely controlled by the intellect. • “[A]uthority” and “intellectual climate” make a big difference: “fear and hope, prejudice and passion, imitation and partisanship, the circumpressure of our caste and set” • Our foundational beliefs (e.g., in truth itself) are just “passionate affirmation[s] of desire, in which our social system backs us up” • We disbelieve “facts and theories for which we have no use”

  37. Stating the thesis • Evaluating our psychology • So apparently, as a matter of fact, our beliefs are influenced by lots of non-intellectual factors. • Is this a bad thing? Is it “reprehensible and pathological”? • Or it is okay, to be “treat[ed] as a normal element in making up our minds”? • James thinks it’s okay • “Our passional nature not only lawfully may, but must, decide an option between propositions, whenever it is a genuine option that cannot by its nature be decided on intellectual grounds; for to say, under such circumstances, ‘Do not decide, but leave the question open,’ is itself a passional decision,—just like deciding yes or no,—and is attended with the same risk of losing the truth”

  38. Dogmatism, absolutism,and empiricism • Dogmatism • James is going to work with the assumption that there really is such a thing as truth. • Absolutism • When you get at something true, there is some sort of telltale indication that you’ve gotten it. • James uses the metaphor of a bell that goes off in your head whenever you get knowledge. • He thinks that most of us are absolutists at heart. Even empiricists like Clifford think they know certain things for sure. • Empiricism • But James is an empiricist: he thinks that there is no sure indicator of truth, and that no belief is so sure as to be beyond reinterpretation and correction. • The test of a belief is not whether it comes from some infallible intellectual faculty, but whether it stands up to repeated examination.

  39. Two goals • Epistemology involves two goals: • Gain truth • Avoid error • Ranking these goals • Clifford thinks (according to James) that avoiding error is of supreme importance—he’d give up all chance at gaining truth rather than risk any error. • Others might think gaining truth is more important. • James insists that any such ranking is an “expressio[n] of our passional life”—some people are terrified of believing false things, whereas others feel like it’s no big deal. • He says Clifford’s rule “is like a general informing his soldiers that it is better to keep out of battle forever than to risk a single wound”

  40. Examining agnosticism • James’s strategy • James is going to examine principled agnosticism in the realms of science, morality, and religion. • He’s going to see whether we should be agnostics when confronted with ambiguous evidence. • Science • James will argue that it makes sense to be agnostic on scientific issues when the evidence is ambiguous. • Morality • James will argue that principled agnosticism is absurd in cases of personal relations. • Religion • James will argue that it’s okay to follow pro-religion passions, and that principled agnosticism is an irrational rule.

  41. Science, morality • Science • The options in science are not momentous or forced, so principled agnosticism makes sense as a way of avoiding falsehood. • It’s not like science is so urgent that we need some belief, any belief to get by. • Though it’s nice to have zealous scientists pushing their theories, just as a way of encouraging scientific progress. • Morality • James seems to suggest that both philosophical skepticism about morality and commitment to morality are okay. • With personal relations, having positive hopeful beliefs (“precursive faith”) is a good way of making these beliefs eventually come true. • It would be absurd to wait for evidence as to whether someone likes me before trusting them.

  42. Religion • Essence of religion • First, “the best things are the more eternal things” • Second, “we are better off even now if we believe [the first thing] to be true” • What if religion is true? • The option is momentous: a “vital good” is at stake. • The option is forced: being agnostic is just one more way of missing out on this vital good. • Agnosticism isn’t a way of avoiding the options; it’s a way of taking a specific option: “Better risk loss of truth than chance of error”. • It’s not saying the intellect is better than the passions; it’s saying that the fear of error is a better passion than the hope of gaining truth. • Doesn’t “my passional need of taking the world religiously” have any say in the matter?

  43. Religion, cont’d • Personal religion • Now consider that (for most of us) religions present the eternal perfection as somehow ‘personal’. • And the option feels like it’s being proposed to “our active good-will, as if evidence might be forever withheld from us unless we met the hypothesis half-way” • Agnostics might “cut [themselves] off forever from [their] only opportunity of making the gods’ acquaintance” • Principled agnosticism is irrational • If all this is true, then principled agnosticism keeps us from the truth. • And “a rule of thinking which would absolutely prevent me from acknowledging certain kinds of truth if those kinds of truth were really there, would be an irrational rule”

  44. Religion, concluded • Waiting for evidence • James thinks it’s bizarre to say we’re required to wait for the evidence to come in. • It might make sense if we were absolutists, if we thought our intellect would somehow tell us when we had knowledge. • But we’re empiricists, so we don’t expect to know anything for sure. • Tolerance • We shouldn’t criticize each other for making our decisions one way or the other. • “We ought, on the contrary, delicately and profoundly to respect one another’s mental freedom”

  45. Some comments on James • James’s counterexamples • Clifford gives a big universal rule: “it is wrong always, everywhere, and for any one, to believe anything upon insufficient evidence” • One way of understanding James is that he comes up with two kinds of counterexamples to this rule: • Beliefs such that believing them helps make them come true (e.g., social relations). • Beliefs such that the only way to get the relevant evidence is to believe them first (e.g., God). • [I’m taking this from the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy article “Pragmatic Arguments for Belief in God” written by Jeff Jordan]

  46. Some comments on James • Optimistic practical beliefs • People have given other examples of practical beliefs that it’s okay to have (even without sufficient evidence). • The world is an overall nice place. • People can usually be trusted. • Our efforts can make the world a better place. • The problems I experience will not last my whole life. • I can successfully climb up from the edge of this cliff. • These beliefs make your life go much better, the line of thought goes, and so it’s okay to believe them without sufficient evidence.

  47. Some comments on James • Depressive realism • Some evidence in psychology indicates that happy people tend to overestimate their own abilities, reputation, etc. • In contrast, people suffering from depression tend to give relatively accurate estimates. • I’m told this is all extremely controversial, and I have no expertise in the matter. • But perhaps it could lend support to the idea that having unjustified optimistic beliefs makes your life go better.

  48. Objections to James • Optimistic beliefs • It’s unclear whether you need to have optimistic beliefs in order to get the benefits James mentions. • Maybe all you need is a sort of optimistic pretense where you dwell on happy outcomes. • In baseball, do you need to believe “I’m going to hit a home run” or is it enough to focus on that particular outcome? • Perhaps James’s arguments can’t justify religious belief, but only a sort of hopeful pretense (which arguably fits with some traditional notions of faith).

  49. Objections to James • Fear of false beliefs • James says Clifford is against beliefs based on insufficient evidence because Clifford suffers from a pathological fear of false beliefs. • James also says that principled agnostics in general have nothing to back up their position but a fear of false beliefs. • But first, that’s probably a misinterpretation of Clifford—what Clifford is worried about is the destructive consequences for society if people stop respecting truth and evidence. • And second, a principled agnostic needn’t take avoiding false beliefs as the one supreme goal of epistemology—she might argue that her agnostic methods will give us the best mix of gaining true beliefs and avoiding false beliefs. • That way, an agnostic might have something better than a dubious passion backing up her recommended methods.

  50. Objections to James • Are religious beliefs good? • James sometimes seems to assume that religious beliefs make things better. • After all, he focuses on our right to believe good, nice, optimistic things. • Presumably, for example, James would not defend a racist’s right to follow his racist passions and believe that certain races have genetically lower IQ’s. • Now, religious beliefs like “God loves us and wants us to be nice” are hard to worry about. • But when we get to more detailed, real-world religious beliefs, it’s highly controversial whether they’re good, whether they make things better.

More Related