330 likes | 612 Views
Chapter Four: Decision Making Under Uncertainty ( Econ 512): Economics of Financial Markets Dr. Reyadh Faras. Risk and Uncertainty. Knight (1921): Risk: applies to events for which objective probabilities can be assigned.
E N D
Chapter Four: Decision Making Under Uncertainty(Econ 512): Economics of Financial Markets Dr. ReyadhFaras
Risk and Uncertainty Knight (1921): • Risk: applies to events for which objective probabilities can be assigned. • Uncertainty: : applies to events for which objective probabilities cannot be assigned, or for which it would not make sense to assign them. • Keynes (1936): • A game of chance is Risky because, although the outcome of any one trial is unknown in advance, repetition of the game a large number of times enables observed relative frequencies to be interpreted sensibly as objective probabilities. Econ 512 Dr. Reyadh Faras
Uncertain events are those that cannot be repeated in any controlled way, thus rendering the calculation of relative frequencies difficult, if not impossible. • Insurance markets aside, most financial markets involve uncertainty rather than risk, in the sense that relative frequencies are not readily available to estimate probabilities. • Most applications in finance permit the estimation of probabilities from past data or other info. • Financial analysis is located somewhere a long the spectrum between two polar extremes, one allows for calculating frequencies while the other doesn’t. Econ 512 Dr. Reyadh Faras
4.1 The Stat-preference Approach (SPA) 4.1.1: Modelling Uncertainty • The SPA comprises three basic ingredients: • State of the world, denoted by set S = {s1, s2,..sℓ}. It describes some contingency that could occur. • Actions, describe all relevant aspects of the decision that are made before the state of the world is revealed. They describe choice of assets. • Consequences, express the outcomes of an action corresponding to each state of the world. They are represented by a list, each element of which is the total value of the portfolio in the corresponding state. Econ 512 Dr. Reyadh Faras
If (c) denotes a consequence and (a) denotes an action, then the three components of the theory are related by a function of (sk) and (a) such that c = f(sk, a). Function f(.,.) maps states and actions into the space of consequences. • In portfolio selection, the function links the amount of each asset held (the action) to each asset’s payoff in every state, and hence to the consequence (terminal wealth). • In the state-preference model, each individual has a utility function the value of which serves to rank all the possible consequences. Econ 512 Dr. Reyadh Faras
u = U(f(s1, a), f(s2, a), …, f(sℓ, a)) • The function U(.,.,.,.) differs across individuals. • The individual’s decision problem is to maximize utility,u, by choosing a feasible action which is a portfolio that satisfies the individual’s wealth constraint, and other constraints. • At date (0), today, investors have to make decisions not knowing which of the six states will occur at date (2). • At date (1), it becomes known that one of the events has occurred. • Finally at date (2) the state is revealed. Econ 512 Dr. Reyadh Faras
For simplicity, it is assumed that investors make decisions with respect to a single future date. • The payoff on the (n) assets in the (ℓ) possible state can be arranged in a payoff array. • Rows correspond to states and columns to assets. • vkj is the payoff to a unit of asset j if state k occurs Econ 512 Dr. Reyadh Faras
Let pj denote the price of asset (j) observed today. Then the rate of return on asset (j) in the state (k) is defined by: rkj = (vkj - pj) / pj = (vkj / pj) -1 • The gross rate of return on asset j, Rkj, is: Rkj ≡ (1+rkj)= vkj / pj • Risk-free asset has the same payoff in each state, is denoted with subscript (0), with payoff (v0) in every state and rate of return: r0 = (v0/p0) - 1 Econ 512 Dr. Reyadh Faras
Suppose there is an asset that has a positive payoff of one unit of wealth in a particular state, k, and zero in every other state. • This asset could play the role of an insurance policy; the purchase of which allows the investor to offset any adverse consequences in state k, only. • Assume that one such asset exists for every state. • Investors can insure against the adverse consequences of every possible contingency. • Conditional on the occurrence of any state, investors could be certain of obtaining a known payoff, the cost of which is the asset’s price (or insurance premium). Econ 512 Dr. Reyadh Faras
The presence of such an asset for every state is sufficient for the existence of a complete set of asset markets. • Otherwise, asset markets are said to be incomplete • Completeness is an idealization, and useful as a benchmark against which more realistic circumstances can be evaluated. Econ 512 Dr. Reyadh Faras
4.1.2 Decision making under uncertainty • Denote terminal wealth as Wk, the investor’s utility function is defined over the consequences, Wk , k = 1, 2, ..., ℓ: u = U(W1 ,W2 , ..., Wℓ ) Wk ≡ f(sk, a) • U(.) is similar to standard consumer theory, but in the presence of uncertainty, the investor must make a decision before the state is revealed. So, he must weigh up the consequences across all the conceivable states. Econ 512 Dr. Reyadh Faras
The wealth constraint states that the investor’s outlay on assets equals initial wealth: p1x1 + p2x2 + …+ pnxn = A • Where (A) is the initial wealth and (xj)s denote the number of units of each asset in the portfolio, so that (pjxj)is the amount of wealth devoted to asset j= 1, 2, …n. • The portfolio is linked to terminal wealth via the payoffs of each asset in each state of the world: Wk = vk1 x1 + vk2 x2 + …+ vkn xn (k = 1, 2, ..., ℓ) which is the sum of the payoff of each state multiplied by the chosen amount of the asset. Econ 512 Dr. Reyadh Faras
The result is a portfolio decision in which the amount of each asset held depends on asset prices, initial wealth and preferences. • The analysis can be extended to cover a multiperiod horizon, generalizing the single period decision problem described so far. • In this case, preferences (and utility) depend on the levels of wealth in all states and all dates. • The wealth constraint must be modified to reflect the opportunities for the investor to transfer wealth from one period to the next. Econ 512 Dr. Reyadh Faras
4.2 The expected utility hypothesis (EUH) 4.2.1 Assumptions of the EUH • Probability is completely absent from the analysis in the state preference model. • The EUH approach permits a role for probability (by assigning probabilities to states of the world) to yield more definite implications. • By attaching prob. to each state, the EUH enables a distinction to be drawn between the decision maker’s beliefs (expressed by probabilities) about which state will occur and preferences about how the decision maker orders the consequences of different actions. Econ 512 Dr. Reyadh Faras
The implications of the EUH emerge by imposing a number of assumptions: • Irrelevance of common consequences. The decision maker orders the actions independently of the common consequences for states not in the event. • Preferences are independent of beliefs. Preferences over consequences for the given state are independent of the state in which they occur. Decision maker cares only about the consequence not the label (e.g. k) of the state in which it is received. Econ 512 Dr. Reyadh Faras
Beliefs are independent of consequences. The decision maker’s degree of belief about whether a state will occur is independent of the consequences in the state. • Together, the three assumptions imply that: • The decision maker acts as if a probability is assigned to each state. • There exists a function that is dependent only on the outcomes. • The decision maker orders the actions according to the expected value of the utility function. Econ 512 Dr. Reyadh Faras
Formally, the EUH implies that: u = U(W1 ,W2 , ..., Wℓ ) = π1 u(W1) + π2 u(W2) + …+ πℓ u(Wℓ) where πk is the probability that the investor assigns to state sk. • The u(.) is the same for all states, although the value of its arguments, wk, generally differs across states. • But probabilities and u(.) are allowed to differ across investors. • Assume u/ (W) > 0, meaning that investors prefer more wealth to less. Econ 512 Dr. Reyadh Faras
The EUH is written as stating that actions are ordered according to E[u(W)], where E[.] denotes the operation of summing over the product of probabilities and utilities. • The EUH asserts that actions are chosen to maximize expected utility: E[u(W)] ≡ π1 u(W1) + π2 u(W2) + …+ πℓ u(Wℓ) Econ 512 Dr. Reyadh Faras
4.2.3 Portfolio selection in the EUH • The portfolio selection problem can be stated as: choose the portfolio of assets to maximize expected utility subject to the wealth constraint. • This is the static problem: it does not address the issues of (a) revising decisions overtime, or (b) the possibility that the investor wishes to consume some wealth before the terminal date. • The analysis is expressed in terms of rates of return and proportions of initial wealth invested in assets. Thus, terminal wealth is: W = (1+rP) A Econ 512 Dr. Reyadh Faras
The Fundamental Valuation Relationship • Every portfolio that maximizes expected utility must satisfy a condition called the fundamental valuation relationship (FVR). • The FVR is the set of first order conditions for maximizing expected utility, one for each asset. • Its general form is: E[(1+rj)H]=1 j=1,2, …, n • H is a random variable that varies across states. • If the investor devotes one additional unit of wealth to asset j. • The payoff is (1+rj) and the increment to expected utility is E[(1+rj) u/ (W)]. Econ 512 Dr. Reyadh Faras
It means: weight the utility increment in each state by the state’s probability and sum over the states. • At a maximum of expected utility it is necessary that the expected utility increment is the same, say λ, for each asset, so that E[(1+rj) u/ (W)] = λj=1,2, …, n • If this equation does not hold, then expected utility can be increased by shifting wealth from those assets with low values of E[(1+rj) u/ (W)] to those with high values. • Only when equality holds for every asset can expected utility be at a maximum. Econ 512 Dr. Reyadh Faras
λis the increment to expected utility resulting from a small increase in initial wealth (i.e. E[u/ (W)]). • At a maximum of expected utility, the expected marginal utility of wealth must equal the increment to expected utility from a small change in the holding of any asset; otherwise, expected utility is not at a maximum. • The FVR in the present of a risk –free asset is: E[(rj – r0) H] = 0j=1,2, …, n • The FVR provides a set of necessary conditions for a maximum. Econ 512 Dr. Reyadh Faras
The 2nd order conditions, together with the FVR, provide necessary and sufficient conditions that a solution of the FVR constitutes a maximum of expected utility. • The 2nd order conditions amount to the requirement that u//(W) < 0; that is, that the investor is risk-averse. Econ 512 Dr. Reyadh Faras
Risk neutrality • The case of risk neutrality (u//(W)=0) implies that the marginal utility of wealth is independent of wealth – say u/(W) = c, a positive constant. • This means that: E[(rj – r0) u/ (W)] = 0 c E[(rj – r0)] = 0 E[rj ] = r0 j=1,2, …, n • The equation involves no choice variable of the individual, it either holds or it does not. Econ 512 Dr. Reyadh Faras
If it doesn’t hold, the investor can borrow at r0 and invest an unbounded amount in any asset for which E[rj]> r0; • and short sell an unbounded amount of any asset for which E[rj]< 0, • the proceeds being invested at the risk-free rate, r0. • This implies that no solution to the maximization problem unless E[rj ]=r0 holds; (i.e. the expected return on every asset equals the rate of return on the risk-free asset). Econ 512 Dr. Reyadh Faras
In such an equilibrium, risk neutral investors are indifferent about which asset to hold. • It may seem that a world of uncertainty with risk neutral investors would look rather like a world of certainty (asset payoffs not differ across states). • But, E[rj ]=r0 involves an expectation. • Exactly one state will be realized, and almost surely the actual excess return for asset j will be negative or positive (not zero). • The expectation may be equal to r0 but the actual outcome, when the state is revealed, may will differ. In this case risk is present (future is unknown) even if investors choose to ignore it. Econ 512 Dr. Reyadh Faras
4.4 The Mean-variance Model 4.4.1 The Mean-variance approach to decision making • The EUH remains a general rule for decision making unless a specific form is assumed for the von Neumann-Morgenstern utility function. • One form is that u(.) is quadratic in wealth. Expected utility can be written as a function of the expected value (mean) and the variance (or standard deviation) of terminal wealth. • Hence the name “mean-variance analysis” for a framework that greatly facilitates the construction of optimal portfolios. Econ 512 Dr. Reyadh Faras
Denote the expected value of terminal wealth by E[W] and its variance by var[W] ≡ E[(W – E[W])2]. • If u(.) is quadratic, the expected value of u(W) is a function of E[W] and var[W]: E[u(W)] = F(E[W], var[W]) Econ 512 Dr. Reyadh Faras
4.4.3 The FVR in the Mean-variance model • The FVR can be written as: μj – r 0 = μP – r 0 j= 1, 2, …, n (4.15) σjP / σPσP • Where (σjP) denotes the covariance between the rate of return on asset j and the rate of return on the portfolio as a whole. • The ratio (σjP / σP) equals the increment to risk (as expressed by σP) associated with an incremental change to the proportion of asset j in the portfolio. Econ 512 Dr. Reyadh Faras
Thus, the FVR states that each asset’s expected rate of return in excess of the risk-free rate, μj–r0, per unit of its contribution to overall risk, σjP / σP, is the same for all assets – a necessary condition for a mean-variance optimum. • Investor’s preferences (attitudes to risk) do not appear in expression (4.15). • The equalities depend only on beliefs (expressed in terms of means, variances and covariances of assets’ rates of return). • This implies that there is a role of preferences separate from the role of beliefs. Econ 512 Dr. Reyadh Faras
For a mean-variance investor, portfolio selection is an outcome of a two-stage process: • . Choose a portfolio that satisfies the FVR conditions, (4.15). This portfolio takes a very special form, consisting of only two special assets, which are themselves portfolios of assets. . If a risk-free asset is available, one of the two special assets can be chosen to comprise just the risk-free asset alone. . Investor preferences are not relevant in constructing the special assets; their composition depends only on means, variances and covariances that can be estimated from observed data. Econ 512 Dr. Reyadh Faras
According to investor preferences, choose the optimal portfolio that optimizes these preferences (i.e. that reaches the highest feasible indifference curve). • The practical importance of this approach is that it is often reasonable to assume that the first stage is the same for all investors who have the same information, while investors can be allowed to possess their own, unique preferences (expressing attitudes to risk) in the second stage. Econ 512 Dr. Reyadh Faras