1 / 18

G601, IO I Eric Rasmusen, erasmuse@indiana 27 September 2006 (revised after class) RISK

G601, IO I Eric Rasmusen, erasmuse@indiana.edu 27 September 2006 (revised after class) RISK. Readings.

bevis
Download Presentation

G601, IO I Eric Rasmusen, erasmuse@indiana 27 September 2006 (revised after class) RISK

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. G601, IO I Eric Rasmusen, erasmuse@indiana.edu 27 September 2006 (revised after class) RISK

  2. Readings • 26 September, Tuesday. Risk I have posted some notes on the math of defining risk aversion.My new notes are on my weblog and at risk.htm.I have other weblog entries that I might talk about on prospect-theory-and-loss-aversion, on Gollier's table-to-check-your-own-level of risk aversion, and on Knightian-risk-and-uncertainty discussed using two-card-bets.For reference: "When Does Extra Risk Strictly Increase the Value of Options?" Eric Rasmusen, forthcoming in The Review of Financial Studies. • Due: Problem Set 3: 4.5, 5.4, 6.3, and 6.4. Answers are (or will be) here.

  3. Handouts Hand in Problem Set 3: 4.5, 5.4, 6.3, and 6.4.

  4. The idea of risk aversion is that people like to keep their consumption at a steady level rather than up and down. They prefer to consume $50,000 per year rather than $10,000 one year and $90,000 the next. • The conventional way to represent this is with a strictly concave utility function, such as • U = log(C) • If the utility function is concave like this, then from any starting point a loss of $1 hurts more than a gain of $1 helps.

  5. Caring about Probabilities of Probabilities Suppose Jack might earn $100, $200, $300, or $400, with equal probabilities, an expected wealth of $250. His information partition is (100,200,300,400)-- he can't rule out anything. Jack is very risk averse, so his utilities from known wealths are U(100) = 0 - eU(200) = 100 - eU(300) = 120 - eU(400) = 128 - e, where e is the number of hours he works painting a house.

  6. The Decision Tom offers to tell Jack whether his wealth will either low or high, but not the precise level, if in exchange Jack will spend 2 hours painting Tom's house. Thus, Jack can get the information partition (100,200), (300,400). Should he accept?

  7. Expected Utility Calculations Originally, Jack’s expected utility is .25(0) + .25(100) + .25(120) + .25 (128) = 81 If he pays the 2 hours, his expected utility is -2 + .5[.5U(100)+ .5 U(200) ]+ .5[.5U(300)+ .5 U(400) ] which equals -2 + .25U(100) + .25 U(200) .25U(300) + .25 U(400) which equals -2 + .25(0) + .25(100) + .25(120) + .25 (128) = -2 + 81 = 79.

  8. Reducing Risk Resolving subjective uncertainty in beliefs is different from reducing risk. Suppose Jack could pay 2 hours to change the probability distribution to (.5 probability of $200, .5 probability of $300) His expected utility would be -2 + .5 (100) + .5 (120) = -2 + 110 = 108 (better than 81) But that is not just a change in his beliefs (though they would change too). It is a change in the probabilities of various amounts of cash he might receive. He has ruled out getting a mere $100.

  9. Anxiety Another way to look at all this is that using Expected Utility Theory, Jack cares only about end states, not about his beliefs along the way. His utility from getting $400 on Friday is entirely pleasure that he gets on Friday when he receives the cash (or, better, when he spends the cash). He get no pleasure on Tuesday, Wednesday, or Thursday from anticipating his happiness on Friday. We could model anxiety earlier in the week about the uncertainty, but it would take a different model. We could, in the example earlier, say that today, before Jack knows his future wealth, he gets immediate utility of -20*(4-N) if his information partition has N information sets. Then, it would make sense for Jack to pay 20 hours of labor to increase N from 1 to 2, because it would cost 2 in utility and gain 20.

  10. Anxiety In addition to the Friday utilities above, Jack might have Tuesday utility of V(100) = -400V(200) = 100V(300) = 120V(400) = 126 from perfect information on Tuesday, and from coarser info: V(100,200) = -300V(300,400) = 122 V(100,200,300,400) = 0 The expected utility gain as a result of getting better information would then be 0 + .5(-300) + .5 (122) = -150+ 61 = -91.

  11. LOSS AVERSION Suppose Joe makes $500/month payments for his car. If he makes $10/month less, he is in trouble. If he makes $20/month less, that isn't much worse. Hence, his behavior will seem to violate the assumption of concave utility. Suppose he has a 5% chance of losing $10 and a 5% chance of losing $20. He would prefer to have a 1% chance of losing $10 and an 8% chance of losing $20. He is positively risk loving! On the other hand, suppose this person starts to make $10/month more In the long run, when his car needs replacing, he will smoothly change to $510/month. (here, use my old weblog entry on prospect theory)

  12. Diversification reduces risk Apex stock: $0 or $3 with equal probability Brydox stock: $0 or $3 with equal probability A share of stock costs $1. You have $6 to invest. (X) If you invest in 6 shares of Brydox, your end wealth is either $0 or $18, an expected value of $9. (Y) If you invest in 3 shares of Apex and 3 of Brydox, your end wealth is either $0, $9, $9, or $18, with equal probabilities, an expected value of $9. The diversified strategy is less risky. Thus, if there are lots of independent assets, you should spread your investment across all of them. The risk from any 1 company's behavior would be trivial. Thus, you would be happy for that company to ignore risk and simply to maximize its expected value.

  13. Combination of risk does not reduce risk: Only division does Suppose you could invest in the stock of Brydox, which yields either $0 or $3 with equal probability, or the stock of Brydox, which also yields either $0 or $3 with equal probability, but with independent probability. A share of stock costs $1, and you have $6 to invest. All this is the same as in my previous example. Now, however, you are thinking of investing either (1) $3 in Apex and $3 in cash, OR (2) $3 in Apex and $3 in Brydox. Which is less risky? If you invest in both companies, will the risks tend to cancel out?

  14. The Fallacy of Large Numbers (A) One strategy is to invest $3 in Apex and $3 in cash. This will have a return of $3 or $12, with equal probability. the expected return will be $7.50. (B) The other strategy is to invest $3 in Apex and $3 in Brydox. This will have a return of $0, $9, $9, or $18, with equal probabilities, as we found earlier. The expected return will be $9. If you were risk neutral or slightly risk averse, you'd choose strategy (B) But suppose your utility function was the following strictly concave function: U = 100 + log(C) if C greater than 2 U = log (C) if C less than or equal to 2 That's discontinuous, but there's nothing wrong with that. The main thing for this person is to avoid consumption of less than 2. Thus, he would prefer strategy (A). (Doug Diamond, Paul Samuelson)

  15. Applications Insurance companies don’t work by adding up risks that cancel out. They work by dividing risk among lots of policyholders or stockholders. Diversification across time is a misleading idea. It is not true that it’s safe to invest in stocks so long as you keep your money in for 50 years, because historically no 50-year period has ever had negative stock returns. We’d expect that over 50 years the return would be very close to the average per decade– say, a 90% chance of that. But there would be some chance of a truly horrendous loss from being unlucky in each of those 50 years. And we’re not likely to observe that bad luck in many 50-year periods– a “peso problem”. This is also related to the “Gambler’s Ruin” paradox that if you keep taking gambles with better than fair returns, you’ll go bankrupt eventually with probability one.

  16. Housing as Investment • Suppose I have $40,000 per year in labor income and $100,000 in wealth. This year, I have two choices. • I could invest $100,000 in bonds for a safe 10% return, and pay $10,000 in rent for a house. • B. I could invest $100,000 in a house and not pay rent. House prices swing wildly, between $80,000 and $120,000, with an expected future price of $100,000.

  17. Course Website A link to the course website http://www.rasmusen.org/g601/0.g601.htm

More Related