1 / 38

First-Order Logic

First-Order Logic. Limitations of propositional logic. Suppose you want to say “All humans are mortal” In propositional logic, you would need ~6.7 billion statements Suppose you want to say “Some people can run a marathon” You would need a disjunction of ~6.7 billion statements.

dani
Download Presentation

First-Order Logic

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. First-Order Logic

  2. Limitations of propositional logic • Suppose you want to say “All humans are mortal” • In propositional logic, you would need ~6.7 billion statements • Suppose you want to say “Some people can run a marathon” • You would need a disjunction of ~6.7 billion statements

  3. First-order logic • Propositional logic assumes the world consists of atomic facts • First-order logic assumes the world contains objects, relations, and functions

  4. Syntax of FOL • Constants:John, Sally, 2, ... • Variables:x, y, a, b,... • Predicates:Person(John), Siblings(John, Sally), IsOdd(2), ... • Functions:MotherOf(John), Sqrt(x), ... • Connectives:, , , ,  • Equality:= • Quantifiers:,  • Term: Constant or Variableor Function(Term1, ... , Termn) • Atomic sentence:Predicate(Term1, ... , Termn)or Term1 = Term2 • Complex sentence: made from atomic sentences using connectives and quantifiers

  5. Semantics of FOL • Sentences are true with respect to a model and an interpretation • Model contains objects (domainelements) and relations among them • Interpretation specifies referents for constantsymbols→objects predicatesymbols→relations functionsymbols→ functional relations • An atomic sentence Predicate(Term1, ... , Termn) is true iffthe objects referred to by Term1, ... , Termnare in the relation referred to by predicate

  6. Universal quantification • x P(x) • Example: “Everyone at UNC is smart” x At(x,UNC)  Smart(x) Why not x At(x,UNC)  Smart(x)? • Roughly speaking, equivalent to the conjunction of all possible instantiations of the variable: At(John, UNC)  Smart(John)  ... At(Richard, UNC)  Smart(Richard)  ... • x P(x)is true in a model m iffP(x)is true with x being each possible object in the model

  7. Existential quantification • x P(x) • Example: “Someone at UNC is smart” x At(x,UNC)  Smart(x) Why not x At(x,UNC)  Smart(x)? • Roughly speaking, equivalent to the disjunction of all possible instantiations: [At(John,UNC)  Smart(John)]  [At(Richard,UNC)  Smart(Richard)]  … • x P(x) is true in a model m iffP(x)is true with x being some possible object in the model

  8. Properties of quantifiers • x y is the same as yx • x yis the same as yx • x yis not the same as yx x y Loves(x,y) “There is a person who loves everyone” yx Loves(x,y) “Everyone is loved by at least one person” • Quantifier duality: each quantifier can be expressed using the other with the help of negation x Likes(x,IceCream) x Likes(x,IceCream) x Likes(x,Broccoli) xLikes(x,Broccoli)

  9. Equality • Term1= Term2is true under a given model if and only if Term1and Term2refer to the same object • E.g., definition of Sibling in terms of Parent: x,ySibling(x,y)  [(x = y)  m,f(m = f)  Parent(m,x)  Parent(f,x)  Parent(m,y)  Parent(f,y)]

  10. Using FOL: The Kinship Domain • Brothers are siblings x,y Brother(x,y) Sibling(x,y) • “Sibling” is symmetric x,y Sibling(x,y)  Sibling(y,x) • One's mother is one's female parent m,c(Mother(c) = m)  (Female(m)  Parent(m,c))

  11. Why “First order”? • FOL permits quantification over variables • Higher order logics permit quantification over functions and predicates: P,x [P(x)  P(x)] x,y (x=y)  [P (P(x)P(y))]

  12. Inference in FOL • All rules of inference for propositional logic apply to first-order logic • We just need to reduce FOL sentences to PL sentences by instantiating variables and removing quantifiers

  13. Reduction of FOL to PL • Suppose the KB contains the following: x King(x)  Greedy(x)  Evil(x) King(John) Greedy(John) Brother(Richard,John) • How can we reduce this to PL? • Let’s instantiate the universal sentence in all possible ways: King(John)  Greedy(John)  Evil(John) King(Richard)  Greedy(Richard)  Evil(Richard) King(John) Greedy(John) Brother(Richard,John) • The KB is propositionalized • Proposition symbols are King(John), Greedy(John), Evil(John), King(Richard), etc.

  14. Reduction of FOL to PL • What about existential quantification, e.g., x Crown(x) OnHead(x,John) ? • Let’s instantiate the sentence with a new constant that doesn’t appear anywhere in the KB: Crown(C1) OnHead(C1,John)

  15. Substitution • Substitution of variables by ground terms: SUBST({v/g},P) • Result of SUBST({x/Harry, y/Sally}, Loves(x,y)): Loves(Harry,Sally) • Result of SUBST({x/John}, King(x)  Greedy(x)  Evil(x)): King(John)  Greedy(John)  Evil(John)

  16. Universal instantiation (UI) • A universally quantified sentence entails every instantiation of it: v P(v)SUBST({v/g}, P(v)) for any variable v and ground term g • E.g., x King(x)  Greedy(x)  Evil(x) yields: King(John)  Greedy(John)  Evil(John) King(Richard)  Greedy(Richard)  Evil(Richard) King(Father(John))  Greedy(Father(John))  Evil(Father(John))

  17. Existential instantiation (EI) • An existentially quantified sentence entails the instantiation of that sentence with a new constant: v P(v) SUBST({v/C}, P(v)) for any sentence P, variable v, and constant Cthat does not appear elsewhere in the knowledge base • E.g., x Crown(x) OnHead(x,John) yields: Crown(C1) OnHead(C1,John) provided C1 is a new constant symbol, called a Skolem constant

  18. Propositionalization • Every FOL KB can be propositionalized so as to preserve entailment • A ground sentence is entailed by the new KB iffit is entailed by the original KB • Idea: propositionalize KB and query, apply resolution, return result • Problem: with function symbols, there are infinitely many ground terms • For example, Father(X) yields Father(John), Father(Father(John)), Father(Father(Father(John))), etc.

  19. Propositionalization • Theorem (Herbrand 1930): • If a sentence αis entailed by an FOL KB, it is entailed by a finite subset of the propositionalizedKB • Idea: For n = 0 to Infinitydo • Create a propositional KB by instantiating with depth-n terms • See if α is entailed by this KB • Problem: works if α is entailed, loops if α is not entailed • Theorem (Turing 1936, Church 1936): • Entailment for FOL issemidecidable: algorithms exist that say yes to every entailed sentence, but no algorithm exists that also says no to every nonentailedsentence

  20. Review: FOL inference

  21. Propositionalization • Example KB: x King(x)  Greedy(x)  Evil(x) y Greedy(y) King(John) Brother(Richard,John) • What will propositionalization produce? King(John)  Greedy(John)  Evil(John) King(Richard)  Greedy(Richard)  Evil(Richard) Greedy(John) Greedy(Richard) King(John) Brother(Richard,John) • But what if all we want is to prove Evil(John)?

  22. Generalized Modus Ponens (GMP) p1', p2', … , pn', (p1 p2 …  pnq) such that SUBST(θ, pi')= SUBST(θ, pi) for all i SUBST(θ,q) • Used with definite clauses (exactly one positive literal) • All variables assumed universally quantified • Example: p1' is King(John) p1 is King(x) p2' is Greedy(y) p2 is Greedy(x) θis {x/John,y/John} qis Evil(x) SUBST(θ,q)is Evil(John)

  23. Unification UNIFY(α,β) = θ means that SUBST(θ, α) = SUBST(θ, β) p qθ Knows(John,x) Knows(John,Jane) {x/Jane} Knows(John,x) Knows(y,Mary) {x/Mary, y/John} Knows(John,x) Knows(y,Mother(y)) {y/John, x/Mother(John)} Knows(John,x) Knows(x,Mary) {x1/John, x2/Mary} Knows(John,x) Knows(y,z) {y/John, x/z} • Standardizing apart eliminates overlap of variables • Most general unifier

  24. Inference with GMP p1', p2', … , pn', (p1 p2 …  pnq) such that SUBST(θ, pi')= SUBST(θ, pi) for all i SUBST(θ,q) • Forward chaining • Like search: keep proving new things and adding them to the KB until we can prove q • Backward chaining • Find p1, …, pn such that knowing them would prove q • Recursively try to prove p1, …, pn

  25. Example knowledge base • The law says that it is a crime for an American to sell weapons to hostile nations. The country Nono, an enemy of America, has some missiles, and all of its missiles were sold to it by Colonel West, who is American. • Prove that Col. West is a criminal

  26. Example knowledge base It is a crime for an American to sell weapons to hostile nations: American(x)  Weapon(y)  Sells(x,y,z)  Hostile(z)  Criminal(x) Nonohas some missiles x Owns(Nono,x)  Missile(x) Owns(Nono,M1) Missile(M1) All of its missiles were sold to it by Colonel West Missile(x)  Owns(Nono,x)  Sells(West,x,Nono) Missiles are weapons: Missile(x)  Weapon(x) An enemy of America counts as “hostile”: Enemy(x,America)  Hostile(x) West is American American(West) The country Nono is an enemy of America Enemy(Nono,America)

  27. Forward chaining proof American(x)  Weapon(y)  Sells(x,y,z)  Hostile(z)  Criminal(x) Owns(Nono,M1)  Missile(M1) Missile(x)  Owns(Nono,x)  Sells(West,x,Nono) Missile(x)  Weapon(x) Enemy(x,America)  Hostile(x) American(West) Enemy(Nono,America)

  28. Forward chaining proof American(x)  Weapon(y)  Sells(x,y,z)  Hostile(z)  Criminal(x) Owns(Nono,M1)  Missile(M1) Missile(x)  Owns(Nono,x)  Sells(West,x,Nono) Missile(x)  Weapon(x) Enemy(x,America)  Hostile(x) American(West) Enemy(Nono,America)

  29. Forward chaining proof American(x)  Weapon(y)  Sells(x,y,z)  Hostile(z)  Criminal(x) Owns(Nono,M1)  Missile(M1) Missile(x)  Owns(Nono,x)  Sells(West,x,Nono) Missile(x)  Weapon(x) Enemy(x,America)  Hostile(x) American(West) Enemy(Nono,America)

  30. Backward chaining example American(x)  Weapon(y)  Sells(x,y,z)  Hostile(z)  Criminal(x) Owns(Nono,M1)  Missile(M1) Missile(x)  Owns(Nono,x)  Sells(West,x,Nono) Missile(x)  Weapon(x) Enemy(x,America)  Hostile(x) American(West) Enemy(Nono,America)

  31. Backward chaining example American(x)  Weapon(y)  Sells(x,y,z)  Hostile(z)  Criminal(x) Owns(Nono,M1)  Missile(M1) Missile(x)  Owns(Nono,x)  Sells(West,x,Nono) Missile(x)  Weapon(x) Enemy(x,America)  Hostile(x) American(West) Enemy(Nono,America)

  32. Backward chaining example American(x)  Weapon(y)  Sells(x,y,z)  Hostile(z)  Criminal(x) Owns(Nono,M1)  Missile(M1) Missile(x)  Owns(Nono,x)  Sells(West,x,Nono) Missile(x)  Weapon(x) Enemy(x,America)  Hostile(x) American(West) Enemy(Nono,America)

  33. Backward chaining example American(x)  Weapon(y)  Sells(x,y,z)  Hostile(z)  Criminal(x) Owns(Nono,M1)  Missile(M1) Missile(x)  Owns(Nono,x)  Sells(West,x,Nono) Missile(x)  Weapon(x) Enemy(x,America)  Hostile(x) American(West) Enemy(Nono,America)

  34. Backward chaining example American(x)  Weapon(y)  Sells(x,y,z)  Hostile(z)  Criminal(x) Owns(Nono,M1)  Missile(M1) Missile(x)  Owns(Nono,x)  Sells(West,x,Nono) Missile(x)  Weapon(x) Enemy(x,America)  Hostile(x) American(West) Enemy(Nono,America)

  35. Backward chaining example American(x)  Weapon(y)  Sells(x,y,z)  Hostile(z)  Criminal(x) Owns(Nono,M1)  Missile(M1) Missile(x)  Owns(Nono,x)  Sells(West,x,Nono) Missile(x)  Weapon(x) Enemy(x,America)  Hostile(x) American(West) Enemy(Nono,America)

  36. Backward chaining algorithm

  37. Resolution: FOL version p1···pk, q1···qn such that UNIFY(pi, qj) = θ SUBST(θ, p1···pi-1pi+1 ···pkq1···qj-1qj+1···qn) • For example, Rich(x)  Unhappy(x) Rich(Ken) Unhappy(Ken) with θ = {x/Ken} • Apply resolution steps to CNF(KB α); complete for FOL

  38. Resolution proof: definite clauses

More Related