1 / 21

CAS LX 502 Semantics

CAS LX 502 Semantics. 10a. Presupposition 10.2. Presupposition. Frege 1892: Referring expressions (names, definite descriptions) carry the presupposition that they do in fact refer. For a sentence to have a truth value, its presupposition must hold.

dusty
Download Presentation

CAS LX 502 Semantics

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. CAS LX 502Semantics 10a. Presupposition 10.2

  2. Presupposition • Frege 1892: • Referring expressions (names, definite descriptions) carry the presupposition that they do in fact refer. • For a sentence to have a truth value, its presupposition must hold. • A presupposition of a sentence is also a presupposition of its negation.

  3. Presupposition triggers • Lexical triggers: • Definite noun phrases: • The student fell asleep. • The student didn’t fall asleep. • Factive verbs: • Pat wanted to eat a sandwich. • Tracy thought Pat ate a sandwich. • Tracy realized Pat ate a sandwich. • Pat regretted eating a sandwich. • Pat liked eating a sandwich. • Pat ate a sandwich.

  4. Presupposition triggers • Lexical triggers: • Change of state verbs: • Pat stopped eating a sandwich (at 2pm). • Pat started eating a sandwich (at 2pm). • Verbs of judgment: • Tracy blamed Pat for eating the sandwich. • Tracy faults Pat for eating the sandwich.

  5. Presupposition triggers • Structural triggers: • Cleft constructions and focus: • It was Tracy that ate the sandwich. • Tracy ate the sandwich. • The sandwich was eaten. • It was the sandwich that Tracy ate. • What Tracy ate was the sandwich. • Tracy ate the sandwich. • Tracy ate something. • Too, even: • Even Tracy ate a sandwich. • Tracy ate a sandwich too.

  6. Presupposition survival • Families of sentences. • The Queen of America is bald. • The Queen of America isn’t bald. • Is the Queen of America bald? • Perhaps the Queen of America is bald. • If the Queen of America is bald, I will not wear a wig. • Joan has stopped drinking wine for breakfast. • Joan hasn’t stopped drinking wine for breakfast. • Has Joan stopped drinking wine for breakfast? • Perhaps Joan has stopped drinking wine for breakfast. • If Joan has stopped drinking wine for breakfast, I will celebrate.

  7. Non-presupposition non-survival • Families of sentences. • It’s cold in here. • It’s not cold in here. • Is it cold in here? • Perhaps it’s cold in here. • If it’s cold in here, John loses the bet. • Rocky is a squirrel. • Rocky is not a squirrel. • Is Rocky a squirrel? • Perhaps Rocky is a squirrel. • If Rocky is a squirrel, I will celebrate.

  8. Non-presupposition survival • Families of sentences. • Pat, who bought something here, ate lunch. • Pat, who bought something here, didn’t eat lunch. • Did Pat, who bought something here, eat lunch? • Perhaps Pat, who bought something here, ate lunch. • If Pat, who bought something here, ate lunch, I will not cook the spinach. • What Pat bought here was a fork. • What Pat bought here wasn’t a fork. • Was what Pat bought here a fork? • Perhaps what Pat bought here was a fork. • If what Pat bought here was a fork, I will celebrate.

  9. So… • The “families of sentences” test can tell us when something is not a presupposition (a presupposition will always survive). • Or will it? • The Queen of America isn’t bald—there is no Queen of America.

  10. Metalinguistic negation, etc. • Matt [groaning] isn’t standing over there, Matt [grayning] is. • He isn’t adequate at painting eggs—he’s fantastic at it. • Objecting to the sentence, on various grounds (pronunciation, implicature, connotation, register, …). • Usually comes with a special intonation. • If the Queen of America just opened the window, America must have a Queen.

  11. ps projection: holes and plugs • Joan has stopped drinking wine for breakfast. • Joan previously drank wine for breakfast. • Pat knows that Joan has stopped drinking wine for breakfast. • Joan previously drank wine for breakfast. • Pat believes that Joan has stopped drinking wine for breakfast. • (No presupposition) • Plugs:Do not let presuppositions through (believe) • Holes:Let presuppositions through (know)

  12. ps projection: filters • JOHN drinks too. • JOHN drinks too and Mary doesn’t like it. • Bill is not present and JOHN drinks too. • Somebody else drinks besides John. • Bill drinks and JOHN drinks too. • No constraint on the context? • If JOHN drinks too, then the bottle will not last long. • If the bottle is already empty, then JOHN drinks too. • Somebody else drinks besides John. • If Bill drinks, then JOHN drinks too. • No constraint on the context? • Generalization so far: pq and pq inherit the presuppositions of both p and qexcept any pss of q entailed by p. Conjunctions and conditionals are filters (letting some pss through and others not).

  13. ps projection: filters refined • If there is a depression, the president of GM will lose his job too. • Someone besides the president of GM will lose his/her job? • Well, no, not really. But why? There being a depression doesn’t logically entail that someone loses his/her job. • But the normal context is one in which it is assumed that when there is a depression, many people lose their jobs. In that context, p entails the presupposition of q—and so it is filtered out. • If there is a thunderstorm, the president of GM will lose his job too. • Filter out any ps of q which is entailed by the context+p.

  14. ps projection: local contexts • If there is a depression, the president of GM will lose his job too. • Someone besides the president of GM will lose his/her job? • A way to look at this: local contexts • Suppose c is the context, pq is our sentence. • To be felicitous, c must entail ps(p). • Add p to c, and c+p is now the context against which q is evaluated. • To be felicitous, c+p must entail ps(q). • So: in a normal context where when there’s a depression all sorts of people lose their jobs, c+p will be a context in which all sorts of people lose their jobs, and this entails ps(q). So, the overall c is fine so long as c+p entails ps(q).

  15. ps projection: filters refined • Bill is absent and JOHN drinks too • Someone besides John drinks? • Actually, that one was a bit misleading. • A: I need a non-drinker to support me in avoiding alcohol. It is known that Bill does not drink, and you’ve just mentioned the known fact that Mary drinks. • A kind of normal context, compatible. Because ps(q). • B: I need a non-drinker to support me in avoiding alcohol. The only possible reason for anybody to not be present (in this room) is to drink vodka in the other room. • But here, ps(q) seems not to be presupposed. Why? • The difference is that in this context p entails ps(q). • So, really, it didn’t presuppose ps(q) after all, but rather that c+p entails ps(q). If p is deemed irrelevant, then the context by itself has to entail ps(q).

  16. Some difficulties with filters • I haven’t told the truth. • I realize that I haven’t told the truth. • I didn’t realize that I haven’t told the truth. • I regret that I haven’t told the truth. • If JOHN sings too then I will celebrate. • If I regret that I haven’t told the truth, I will confess it to everyone. • If I realize that I haven’t told the truth, I will confess it to everyone. • If Frank realizes that he hasn’t told the truth, he will confess it to everyone.

  17. A cancellation view • Triggers yield potential presuppositions. A potential ps may or may not become an actual ps. In particular, not if it is canceled. This happens when: • The ps is inconsistent with assumptions in the context. • The ps is inconsistent with one of the conversational implicatures of the matrix sentence containing the trigger. • If the problem has been solved, then it is Lauri who solved it. • Implicature: truth value of the problem has been solved (somebody has solved the problem) not assumed.

  18. A cancellation view • Triggers yield potential presuppositions. A potential ps may or may not become an actual ps. In particular, not if it is canceled. This happens when: • The ps is inconsistent with assumptions in the context. • The ps is inconsistent with one of the conversational implicatures of the matrix sentence containing the trigger. • I don’t have a dog. • So at least you don’t have to walk your dog. • Problems here too. • If John has twins, Mary will not like his children.

  19. Projection into one’s beliefs? • The unicorn is waiting in the garden. • #Yet there are no unicorns. • Pat knows that the unicorn is waiting in the garden. • #Yet there are no unicorns. • Pat thinks that the unicorn is waiting in the garden. • Yet there are no unicorns (silly Pat). • #Yet, Pat believes there are no unicorns. • Pat wants the unicorn to sleep in the garden. • If the unicorn is in the garden, Pat will be happy.

  20. Attitude verbs • Patrick wants to sell his cello. • Patrick is under the mistaken belief that he owns a cello, and he wants to sell his cello. • Embed q under an attitude verb (SVq) requires that ps(q) be entailed by S’s beliefs.

  21.         

More Related