420 likes | 689 Views
Classical Logic. Lecture Notes for SWE 623 by Duminda Wijesekera. Propositional and Predicate Logic. Propositional Logic The study of statements and their connectivity structure. Predicate Logic The study of individuals and their properties. Study syntax and semantics for both.
E N D
Classical Logic Lecture Notes for SWE 623 by Duminda Wijesekera Duminda Wijesekera
Propositional and Predicate Logic • Propositional Logic • The study of statements and their connectivity structure. • Predicate Logic • The study of individuals and their properties. • Study syntax and semantics for both. • Propositional logic more abstract and hence less detailed than predicate logic. Duminda Wijesekera
Propositional Logic: Syntax • A collection of atomic propositional symbols. • Say A = { ai : 0 < i }. A special atom _|_for contradiction • A collection of logical connectives. • (and) ^, (or) v, ( not ) , (implies) => • Inductively define propositions as: If X,Y are propositions, so are :– X^ Y, Xv Y, X => Y, X. • Examples: • a1^a2, (a =>a2)v(a3^( a4)) are propositions. Duminda Wijesekera
Propositional Logic: Semantics • A model M of a propositional language consists of • a collection of atoms, say B = { bi : 0 < i }, where_|_ is excluded from B, and • a partial mapping M from A = { ai : 0 < i } to B = { bi : 0 < i }. • If M(ai) e B, we say that ai is true in M. We write “ai is true in M” as M |= ai. (Read M satisfies ai). • |= is referred to asthe satisfaction relation. Duminda Wijesekera
Propositional Semantics: Continued • Extend M, and therefore the satisfaction relation to all propositions using the following inductive definition: • M |= X^ Y iff M |= XandM |= Y. • M |= Xv Y iff M |= XorM |= Y. • M |= X => Y ifM |= XthenM |= Y. • M |= X, if it is not the case thatM |= X. • Notice usage of truth tables Duminda Wijesekera
Propositional Logic: Example • B = { a1, a3} where M given as M(a1) = a1 and M(a2) = a2 has the following properties. • M |= a1 • M |= a1^ a3 • M |= a2 • M |= a2 =>a4 • M does not satisfy the following propositions. • M |= a4 • M |= a1 =>a4 Duminda Wijesekera
Propositional Logic: Proofs • What formulas hold in all models ? • I.e. can we check if a given proposition is true in all models without going through all possible models? • Need proofs to answer this question. • We use Natural Deduction proofs. • Recommended: Read Ch 2 of Logic and Computation by L.C. Paulson. Duminda Wijesekera
Natural Deduction for Prop. Logic • Proofs are trees of formulae made by applying inference rules. • An inference rule is of the form: A1 …… An B • Here A1 ….. An are said to be premises (or antecedents) of the rule, and B is said to be the conclusion (consequent) of the rule. Duminda Wijesekera
Natural Deduction for Prop. Logic • Hence a proofs is a trees whose • Root is the theorem to be proved, • Branches are rules, and • Leaves are the assumptions (axioms) of the proof. • Example • A1 A2 A3 C1 C2 Assumptions B1 B2 Applications of rules D Theorem being proved • There are introduction and elimination rules for each connective in Natural Deduction proof systems. Duminda Wijesekera
Rules for Conjunction • Introduction A B A ^ B • Elimination A ^ BA ^ B A B Duminda Wijesekera
Rules for Disjunction • Introduction A B A v B A v B • Elimination [A] [B] A v B C C C • [X] denotes discharged assumption X. Duminda Wijesekera
Rules for Implication • Introduction [A] B A => B • Elimination (Modus Ponens) A => B A B Duminda Wijesekera
Rules for Negation • B interpreted as ( B => _|_). Hence we get the following rules from those of implication. • Introduction Elimination [B] B B _|_ _|_ ________ B • Special Contradiction Rule: B _|_ __________ B Duminda Wijesekera
Propositional Proofs: Examples • Prove: ( A ^ B ) => (A v B) • Notice: • The outermost connective is =>. Hence, the last step of the proof must be an implication introduction. • That means, we must assume ( A ^ B ) and prove (A v B), and then discharge the assumption by using => introduction rule. • In order to prove (A v B) from ( A ^ B ), we must use v –introduction, and hence must prove either A or B from ( A ^ B ). • This plan forms a skeleton of a proof. Duminda Wijesekera
Prop. Proof: Example Continued • Prove: ( A ^ B ) => (A v B) [A ^ B ] A ^elimination A v B v introduction ( A ^ B ) => (A v B) => introduction • Proofs are analyzed backwards, I.e. start unraveling the logical structure of the conclusion and work backwards to the assumptions. Draw out a plan based on your analysis and write down the formal proof. Duminda Wijesekera
Derived Rules • These are rules derived from other rules. • Example: A ^ B B ^ A • Here is the derivation: A ^ BB ^ A B A^elimination B ^ A ^introduction Duminda Wijesekera
Soundness and Completeness • A rule A1 …… An is said to be sound if for every B model in which all of A1 …… An are true, then so is B. I.e. if M |= A1 , …… , M |= An, then M |= B. • A collection of rules are sound if all rules in the collection is sound. • A collection of rules is complete if M |= A for all models M, then A is provable. I.e. there is a proof of A using the given set of rules. (Denoted |R-- A ) where R is the set of rules. Duminda Wijesekera
Predicate Logic • Language to describe properties of individuals. • Thus, syntax is able to describe individuals, their properties (relationships) and functions. • These are to be thought of as names of individuals, properties (relationships) and functions. • Models are “incarnations” of these individuals, properties (relationships) and functions. • More detailed than propositional logic. Duminda Wijesekera
Predicate Logic: Syntax • A collection of constants– say { ci : i >= 0 }. • Constants are names for individuals. E.g.: 0, 1. • Note: not all individuals in a model have names. • A collection of variables– say { xi : i >= 0 }. • Needed to generically refer to individuals. • Think of them as standing in place of pronouns like it, she. • A collection of function symbols- say { fi : i >= 0 }. • May be of different arities, and may be typed. E.g.: +(x,y) • A collection of predicate symbols- say { pi : i >= 0 }. • May be of different arities. • Encodes properties of individuals. E.g.: prime(x). Duminda Wijesekera
Predicate LogicRecursive Definition of Terms • Every variable is a term. • Every constant is a term. • If fi is an n-ary function symbol and t1, .., tn are terms, then fi(t1, .., tn) is a term. • We use {ti : i <=0 } for the collection of terms. • Examples: • f(x, g(2, y)) is a term, where f, g are function symbols and x, y are variables. • +( x, *(3,y)) is a term in arithmetic usually written as x + (3*y) Duminda Wijesekera
Recursive Definition of Formulas • If pi is an n-ary predicate symbol and t1, .., tn are terms, then pi(t1, .., tn ) is an atomic formula. • If A and B are formulas, then so are: • A^ B, A v B, A, A => B. • xi A(xi), xi A(xi), where xi is a variable. • , are referred to as the universal and existential quantifier, respectively. • A formula that does not have either quantifier is said to be a quantifier free. Duminda Wijesekera
Free and bound Variables • In x A(x), the variable x is said to be bound; meaning the name x plays no significant role. (compare with he, she, it) • A variable x occurs bound in a formula if xor x is a part of it. More precisely, x occurs bound in: • yA(y) or y A(y) if x and y are the same variable. • A if x occurs bound in A. • A^ B, A v B, A => B if x occurs bound in either A or B. Duminda Wijesekera
Substitutions • If A is a formula, t is a term and x is a variable, then A[t/x] is the formula obtained by substituting t for x in A. • A[t1/x1, … tn/xn] is the formula resulting in simultaneously substituting x1, …xn by t1, …tn. • Note: Simultaneous substitution Q(x,y)[x/y,y/x] yields Q(y,x) but iterated substitution Q(x,y)[x/y][y/x] yields Q(y,y). Duminda Wijesekera
Substituting Terms for Variables • In A[t/x], the free variables of t stand the danger of becoming bound in A. Hence, need a precise definition. • If x is y then yA(y) [x/y] is yA(y). If not let z be a fresh variable (I.e. not in t, x) then (yA(y) )[t/x] is z (A(z/y) [t/x]). • Similar definition for y A(y). • Examples: • y (y = 1) [y/y] is y (y = 1). Here x is y and t is x. • y (y+1 > x) [2y+x/x] is z ((z+1>x)[2y+x/x] I.e. z (z+1>2y+x). Here t is (2y+x). Duminda Wijesekera
Substituting Terms Continued • ( A )[t/x] is (A [t/x]) • (A^ B) [t/x] is (A[t/x]^ B[t/x]) • (Av B) [t/x] is (A[t/x]vB[t/x]) • (A=> B) [t/x] is (A[t/x]=> B[t/x]) • Pi(t1, .. tn) [t/x] is Pi(t1[t/x], .. tn[t/x]) for predicate symbol Pi. Duminda Wijesekera
Predicate Logic: Semantics • A model consists of • A set (of individuals), say A = { ai : i >= 0 }. • A set of total functions Fn = { fni : i >= 0 } on A. • I.e. fni(aj) is some ak for every aj. • A set of predicates Pr = { pri : i >= 0 } over A. • Do not have to be total. • Can have many arities. Duminda Wijesekera
Interpreting Syntax • Mapping from Syntax to Semantics: • A mapping mCons : { ci : I >= 0 } to A={ai: i >= 0}. • Need not be ONTO A. I.e. there could be unnamed individuals in the semantic domain. • A mapping mFun : { fi : I >= 0 } to Fn={fni: i >= 0}. • Need not be onto. I.e. there could be unnamed functions in the semantic domain. • A mapping mPred: { pi : I >= 0 } to Pr={pri: i >= 0}. • Need not be onto. I.e. there could be unnamed predicates in the semantic domain. Duminda Wijesekera
Interpreting Formulas: naming • We do not interpret formulas with free variables. • In order to interpret quantified formulas, need to expand the syntax by adding a constant in the syntax for each unnamed individual in the model. • I.e. for each ai for which there is no cj such that Fn(cj ) is ai, add a new constant Cai to the syntax. • Now expand the definition of terms to include these new constants. Let newT = { Nti : i >= 0} be the collection of new terms so defined. Duminda Wijesekera
Interpreting Formulas • Let M be a model. We define M |= F for every quantified formula as follows. • For every n-ary predicate symbol pi , and every sequence of new variable free terms Nt1, … Ntn define M |= pi(Nt1, … Ntn ) if and only if mPred(pi)(Nt1, … Ntn ). • I.e. pi(Nt1, … Ntn ) is true in M if and only if its image under the map mPred holds with parameters Nt1, … Ntn . Duminda Wijesekera
Interpreting Formulas: Continued • For every formula A , M |= y A(y) if and only if M |= A(Nti) for every Nti e newT. • For every formula A , M |= y A(y) if and only if there is some Nti e newT satisfying M |= A(Nti). • M |= A ^ B if M |= A and M |= B . • M |= A v B if M |= A or M |= B. • M |= A => B if when M |= A then M |= B. • M |= A if it is not the case that M |= A. Duminda Wijesekera
Proof Rules for Predicate Logic • Proof rules of introduction and elimination of ^, v, =>, and . • New rules required for introductionand elimination of and quantifiers. Duminda Wijesekera
Proof Rules for • Introduction A(x) provided x is not free in the x A(x) assumptions of A • Elimination x A(x) A[t/x] Duminda Wijesekera
Proof Rules for • Introduction A[t/x] xA(x) • Elimination [A] provided x is not free xA(x) B in B nor in the B assumptions of B apart from A Duminda Wijesekera
An Example Proof • Prove ((x A(x)) ^ B)=> (x (A(x)^ B)) provided that x is not free in B. • Plan: • Since outer connective is =>, need to use => introduction at the last step. Hence can use (x A(x)) ^ B as an assumption for the steps above. • Now in order to get x (A(x)^ B) using introduction, we need to get A[t/x] )^ B. • Can use ^ eliminationto (x A(x)) ^ B and obtain B • Can use x elimination to get A[t/x]. Duminda Wijesekera
Example Proof x A(x) ^ Bx A(x) ^ B x A(x) [A(t/x)] B A(t/x) ^ B x(A(x) ^ B • The other directionof the proof appears in the handout page 32. Duminda Wijesekera
Induction Rule [A(x)] A[0/x] A[x+1/x] A(x) Proviso: x is not free in the assumptions of A[x+1/x] apart from A(x). Duminda Wijesekera
Equality Reasoning • Rules for equality • Reflexivity axiom: t = t. • Symmetry rule: t = u . u = t • Transitivity rule: s = t t = u . s = u • Congruence laws for each function and predicate symbol, or substitution rules. Duminda Wijesekera
Equality Reasoning: Continued • Congruence Law for functions: t1 = u1 …. tn = un f(t1, …., tn) = f(u1, ….,un) • Congruence Law for Predicates: t1 = u1 …. tn = un p(t1, …., tn) p(u1, ….,un) • Substitution Rule: t = u S[t/x] = S[u/x] Duminda Wijesekera
Equality Reasoning: An Example This example is from Page 37, of the Logic handout. x f(x,x) = x f(g(z), g(z)) = g(z) p(f(g(z), g(z)) p(g(z)) p(f(g(z), g(z)) p(g(z)) Duminda Wijesekera
Logic: Suggested Exercises • Go thorough all proofs and suggested exercises in the handout. • Take the midterm and final exams from last semester and attempt the proofs. • Go through the second homework from last semester. • Reference: Chapter 2 of Logic and Computation by L.C. Paulson. Duminda Wijesekera