1 / 20

Probability and Theory Confirmation

Probability and Theory Confirmation. Why making a prediction that is borne out makes a theory more probably true. Probability can be thought of as:. Objective chance Physical propensity Degree of belief Long-run frequency Degree of confirmation. The probability function p(A).

gaerwn
Download Presentation

Probability and Theory Confirmation

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. Probability and Theory Confirmation Why making a prediction that is borne out makes a theory more probably true

  2. Probability can be thought of as: • Objective chance • Physical propensity • Degree of belief • Long-run frequency • Degree of confirmation

  3. The probability function p(A) • Applies to events or propositions A • Yields as output a real number in [0,1] • Linearizes what is otherwise a partial ordering of the propositions • … and must therefore satisfy certain constraints

  4. Constraints on p(A) • 0  p(A)  1 • If |– A , then p(A)=1 • If A |– , then p(A)=0 • If A |– B , then p(A)  p(B)

  5. Lemma 1A |– B B |– Ap(A)=p(B). Proof: By (4) we have p(A)p(B) and p(B)p(A). By anti-symmetry of ,we have p(A)=p(B).

  6. Definition AB is short for (AB)

  7. Definition If 0<p(B) then p(A|B)=p(AB)/p(B)

  8. Theorem 1 (Bayes)0<p(A) 0<p(B)p(A|B)=p(B|A).p(A)/p(B) Under the hypotheses we have, by definition, p(AB)=p(A|B).p(B) and p(BA)=p(B|A).p(A). By Lemma 1, p(AB)=p(BA). Hence p(A|B).p(B)=p(B|A).p(A). Dividing both sides by p(B), the result follows.

  9. Lemma 20<p(B) B |– A0<p(A). Proof: Suppose B|–A. By (4), p(B)  p(A). Now suppose 0<p(B). It follows that 0<p(A).

  10. Theorem 20<p(CB) 0<p(AB)p(A|CB).p(C|B)=p(C|AB).p(A|B) Proof: Suppose 0<p(CB). Note CB|–B. By Lemma 2, 0<p(B). By Lemma 1, p(ACB)=p(CAB). Hence p(ACB)/p(B) = p(CAB)/p(B). Hence p(ACB).p(CB)/p(CB).p(B) = p(CAB).p(AB)/p(AB).p(B). By definition, p(A|CB).p(C|B)=p(C|AB).p(A|B)

  11. Lemma 3B |– A 0<p(B)p(A|B)=1. Proof: Suppose B|–A. Then B is interdeducible with AB. So by Lemma 1 we have p(B)=p(AB). By definition we have p(A|B)=p(AB)/p(B). Substituting, p(A|B)=p(B)/p(B)=1.

  12. Lemma 4A,B |– C 0<p(AB)p(C|AB)=1. Proof: Suppose A,B|–C. Then AB|–CAB. Also, CAB|–AB. So by Lemma 1 we have p(CAB)=p(AB). By definition we have p(C|AB)=p(CAB)/p(AB). Substituting, p(C|AB)=p(AB)/p(AB)=1.

  13. Corollary 1A,B |– C 0<p(CB) 0<p(AB)p(A|CB).p(C|B)=p(A|B). Proof: The two inequalities mean Theorem 2 applies. So p(A|CB).p(C|B)=p(C|AB).p(A|B). But now the deducibility hypothesis means that the factor p(C|AB)=1. The result follows.

  14. Theorem 30<p(HK) H,K |– E p(E|K)<1p(H|EK)>p(H|K). Proof: P(E|HK) exists. Since H,K|–E, we have (by Lemma 4) p(E|HK)=1. We also have HK|–EK. By (4), p(HK)  p(EK). But 0<p(HK). So 0<p(EK). Now Theorem 2 applies: p(H|EK).p(E|K)=p(E|HK).p(H|K). Putting p(E|HK)=1, we get p(H|EK).p(E|K)=p(H|K). But p(E|K)<1. So p(H|EK)>p(H|K).

  15. Title/claim • Comment 1 • Comment 2

  16. Title/claim • Comment 1 • Comment 2

  17. Title/claim • Comment 1 • Comment 2

  18. Title/claim • Comment 1 • Comment 2

  19. Title/claim • Comment 1 • Comment 2

  20. Title/claim • Comment 1 • Comment 2

More Related