90 likes | 101 Views
This paper explores the implementation of rules in Bayes-Nash equilibrium, with a focus on designing mechanisms that achieve optimal outcomes in various settings. It discusses the concept of implementation in Bayes-Nash equilibrium, weaker requirements than dominant strategy implementation, and the possibility of achieving budget balance and Pareto efficiency. The paper also presents the expected externality mechanism and its limitations, as well as the Myerson-Satterthwaite impossibility theorem. It concludes with a discussion on full implementation and virtual implementation.
E N D
Implementation in Bayes-Nash equilibrium Tuomas Sandholm Computer Science Department Carnegie Mellon University
Implementation in Bayes-Nash equilibrium • Goal is to design the rules of the game (aka mechanism) so that in Bayes-Nash equilibrium (s1, …, s|A|), the outcome of the game is f(u1, …, u|A|) • Weaker requirement than dominant strategy implementation • An agent’s best response strategy may depend on others’ strategies • Agents may benefit from counterspeculating each others’ • preferences • rationality • endowments • capabilities … • Can accomplish more than under dominant strategy implementation • E.g., budget balance & Pareto efficiency (social welfare maximization) under quasilinear preferences …
dAGVA expected externality mechanism [d’Aspremont & Gerard-Varet 79; Arrow 79] • Like Groves mechanism, but sidepayment is computed based on agent’s revelation vi , averaging over possible true types of the others v-i • Outcome (x1, x2, ..., xk, m1, m2, ..., m|A| ) • Quasilinear preferences: ui(x, m) = mi + vi(x1, x2, ..., xk) • Utilitarian setting: Social welfare maximizing choice • Outcome s(v1, v2, ..., v|A|) = maxxivi(x1, x2, ..., xk) • Others’ expected welfare when agent i announces vi is (vi) = v-i p(v-i) jivj(s(vi , v-i)) • Measures change in expected externality as agent i changes her revelation • Thrm. Assume quasilinear preferences and independently drawn valuation functions vi. A utilitarian social choice function f: v -> (s(v), m(v)) can be implemented in Bayes-Nash equilibrium if mi(vi)= (vi) + hi(v-i) for arbitrary function h • Unlike in dominant strategy implementation, budget balance achievable • Intuitively, have each agent contribute an equal share of others’ payments • Formally, set hi(v-i) = - [1 / (|A|-1)] ji(vj) • Does not satisfy participation constraints (aka individual rationality constraints) in general • Agent might get higher expected utility by not participating
Myerson-Satterthwaite impossibility • Avrim is selling a car to Tuomas, both are risk neutral, quasilinear • Each party knows his own valuation, but not the other’s valuation • The probability distributions are common knowledge • Want a mechanism that is • Ex post budget balanced • Ex post Pareto efficient: Car changes hands iff vbuyer > vseller • (Interim) individually rational: Both Avrim and Tuomas get higher expected utility by participating than not • Thrm. Such a mechanism does not exist (even if randomized mechanisms are allowed) • This impossibility is at the heart of more general exchange settings (NYSE, NASDAQ, combinatorial exchanges, …) !
Proof • Seller’s valuation is sL w.p. a and sH w.p. (1-a) • Buyer’s valuation is bL w.p. b and bH w.p. (1-b). Say bH > sH > bL > sL • By revelation principle, can focus on truthful direct revelation mechanisms • p(b,s) = probability that car changes hands given revelations b and s • Ex post efficiency requires: p(b,s) = 0 if (b = bL and s = sH), otherwise p(b,s) = 1 • Thus, E[p|b=bH] = 1 and E[p|b = bL] = a • E[p|s = sH] = 1-b and E[p|s = sL] = 1 • m(b,s) = expected price buyer pays to seller given revelations b and s • Since parties are risk neutral, equivalently m(b,s) = actual price buyer pays to seller • Buyer pays what seller gets paid ex post budget balance • E[m|b] = (1-a) m(b, sH) + a m(b, sL) • E[m|s] = (1-b) m(bH, s) + b m(bL, s) • Individual rationality (IR) requires • b E[p|b] – E[m|b] 0 for b = bL, bH • E[m|s] – s E[p|s] 0 for s = sL, sH • Bayes-Nash incentive compatibility (IC) requires • b E[p|b] – E[m|b] b E[p|b’] – E[m|b’] for all b, b’ • E[m|s] – s E[p|s] E[m|s’] – s E[p|s’] for all s, s’ • Suppose a=b= ½, sL=0, sH=y, bL=x, bH=x+y, where 0 < 3x < y. Now, • IR(bL): ½ x – [ ½ m(bL,sH) + ½ m(bL,sL)] 0 • IR(sH): [½ m(bH,sH) + ½ m(bL,sH)] - ½ y 0 • Summing gives m(bH,sH) - m(bL,sL) y-x • Also, IC(sL): [½ m(bH,sL) + ½ m(bL,sL)] [½ m(bH,sH) + ½ m(bL,sH)] • I.e., m(bH,sL) - m(bL,sH) m(bH,sH) - m(bL,sL) • IC(bH): (x+y) - [½ m(bH,sH) + ½ m(bH,sL)] ½ (x+y) - [½ m(bL,sH) + ½ m(bL,sL)] • I.e., x+y m(bH,sH) - m(bL,sL) + m(bH,sL) - m(bL,sH) • So, x+y 2 [m(bH,sH) - m(bL,sL)] 2(y-x). So, 3x y, contradiction. ■
Myerson-Satterthwaite impossibility… • Actually, the impossibility applies to any priors, as long as • the priors’ supports overlap, and • the priors don’t have gaps • The inefficiency is caused by two-sided private information
Full implementation: virtual implementation • Here we don’t necessarily assume that payments are possible • Want to implement so that the right social choice function is achieved in all equilibria • Virtual implementation: relax this by allowing a social choice within ε to be implemented (for all ε > 0) • Thm [Serrano & Vohra GEB 2005]. Consider pure strategies only, finite type spaces, private types, and assume no-total-indifference (i.e., for each agent and each type, there are no ties in expected utility (as long as beliefs are updated using Bayes rule)). A social choice function in such environments is virtually Bayesian implementable iff it satisfies Bayesian incentive compatibility and a condition called virtual monotonicity. • Virtual monotonicity is weak in the sense that it is generically satisfied in environments with at least three alternatives • So, in most environments virtual Bayesian implementation is as successful as it can be (i.e., incentive compatibility is the only condition needed)
Full implementation: subgame perfection(Hart-Moore example of Moore-Repullo mechanism) Mechanism (assumes common knowledge between B and S)