1 / 57

Is a Mental Image Really Mental ?

9th EWIC - Pavia - April 26, 2003. Is a Mental Image Really Mental ?. Alessandro Antonietti - Manuela Cantoia - Barbara Colombo Department of Psychology Cognitive Psychology Laboratory Catholic University of Sacred Heart of Milan.

jensen
Download Presentation

Is a Mental Image Really Mental ?

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. 9th EWIC - Pavia - April 26, 2003 Is a Mental Image Really Mental ? Alessandro Antonietti - Manuela Cantoia - Barbara Colombo Department of Psychology Cognitive Psychology Laboratory Catholic University of Sacred Heart of Milan

  2. The studies presented here originated in the field of developmental psychology, more precisely within the investigation of children’s “discovery” of the mind. In this area researchers are interested in- assessing when and how children come to ascribe mental states to human beings [see subsequent slide ];- assessing what features children attribute to such mental states.

  3. As far as the second issue is concerned, according to Wellman the criteria which allow a Western adult to distinguish between a physical and a mental entity are the following []:

  4. Wellman’s criteria: - mental entities do not afford behavioural-sensory contact - mental entities do not have public existence - mental entities do not have temporally consistent existence - mental entities can be transformed by thinking about them

  5. Wellman claimed that these criteria are mastered by children early in the development. For instance, in a series of experiments Wellman and his collaborators presented pre-schoolers both with the situation of a child who is perceiving an object that is physically present and with the situation of a child who is imagining that object. [] The experimenters asked some questions about the two situations [] :

  6. Wellman & Estes, 1986; Estes et al., 1989; Wolley & Wellman, 1992:

  7. Wellman & Estes, 1986; Estes et al., 1989; Wolley & Wellman, 1992: Can you see it with your eyes ? Can you touch it with your hands ? Can I see it ? Can I touch it ? Can I use it to play ? Just by thinking about it, can you transform it ?

  8. The results of the experiments suggested that even 3-year-olds can give responses consistent with the previously mentioned criteria [].

  9. Wellman & Estes, 1986, Exp. 1, p. 913

  10. Wellman’s claim is that children share the same basic criteria as adults when requested to define a mental experience - such as imagining an object. In fact, the rates of the “correct” responses recorded in children’s samples were close to the perfect rates which Wellman expected to find in adult samples. However, some fortuitous observations we carried out by asking adults informally the same questions posed by Wellman and coworkers to children induced us to cast doubts about this prediction. Thus, we decided to investigate systematically adults’ reactions to Wellman’s questions.

  11. First of all, we collected all the questions asked to children in Wellman’s experiments, by referring them to one (the pen) of the objects considered in such experiments []. Questions concerning the temporal consistency of mental experience were omitted since - as Wellman admitted - some physical entities - such as smoke - do not possess such a feature.

  12. Can you see the pen?Sensory • Can you touch the pen? • Contact • Can you close the pen in a drawer? • Behavioural • Can you move the pen up-down • Can another person see the pen? Public Existence • Can you break the pen? Possible • Transformation • Can you lengthen the pen? Impossible • Can you use the pen Functionto write anything? • Is the pen real? “Ontological” status

  13. Then we tried to follow exactly the same procedure devised by Wellman and to apply it to undergraduates in different disciplines. Students attending psychology courses were excluded. The procedure was as follows []:

  14. Warm up All participants were presented with a picture of a smile and they were asked to close their eyes and to turn the mental image of that smile into a sad expression.

  15. Task “Look at this pen”

  16. Task “Look at this pen” “Close your eyes and try to make a picture of that pen in your head” The nine questions were asked

  17. STUDY 1

  18. In Wellman’s perspective, the expected percentages should be:0 in the first column100 in the last column Surprisingly, undergraduates were far from reaching the predicted values []. Responses given to the question “Can you close the pen into a drawer?” were not considered since many participants did not realised the presence of a drawer in the table used in the experiment; most of them responded “no” because they thought there was not a drawer.

  19. In most cases percentages were not significantly different between the perceptual and the imaginative conditions [].

  20. Why do various percentages in the first column differ from 0? Not because participants were mad, but because they - according to what they reported when requested to give reasons of their responses - felt to be limited by social constraints: for instance they said that they couldn’t touch, move, use and, above all, break the pen since they were not the owner of the pen.In other cases thy answered “no” because they didn’t want or desire to carry out the described action. But, why - contrary to Wellman’s prediction - did undergraduates attributed features such as sensory-behavioural contact and so on to the image of the pen? [](We must also consider the possibility that part of the “no” responses were due to the same extrinsic reasons - social rules, etc. - invoked to explain no responses in the percpetual condition).Is it possible that adults perform worse, from Wellman’s point of view, than pre-schoolers? Further investigation was needed.

  21. STUDY 2 The second experiment was carried out- to replicate these findings through a different design (within subjects)- to ask participants to justify always their responses The procedure was the same as in the previous study, but undergraduates were exposed both to the perceptual and to the imaginative conditions.The order of presentation of the two conditions was randomly changed. After each question, participants were requested to explain why they answered either “yes” or “no”.

  22. Percentages in the Ima-Per condition were similar to those recorded in Study 1. [] However, as far as some questions are concerned, in the Per-Ima condition percentages of the expected responses were higher, near to the predicted values.

  23. Questions about the Imagined Pen:Percentages of Expected Responses under the Two Conditions

  24. In fact, in some cases the percentages of the expected responses significantly differed in the two conditions . [] Presumably, the possibility to compare the imaginative experience to the previous perceptual experience induced participants to recognise the alleged “mental” features (lack of sensory-behavioural contact, availability of impossible transformations, unreality) of the imagery experience. Explanations in term of artifacts produced by the repetition of the same questions can be discarded because these alleged effects did not affect all items. However, why did undergraduates persist in attributing unpredicted features to imagery? The analysis of the justifications given may highlight this issue.

  25. Justifications were classified within a set of well-defined categories which can be collapsed in three main broad categories:[]

  26. Categorisation of Justification Responses to Questions about the Imagined Pen

  27. Justificantions suggested that participants answered the questions by referring to different aspects of the imagery experience. According to the phenomenological tradition, we can distinguish the physical presence from the intentional presence. [] The physical presence concerns external, concrete, material entities.The intentional presence consists in the fact that a physical (or even a abstract-conceptual) entity appears to my consciousness (in the form of a perceptual, imagery, memory, thinking and so on, experience). Within the intentional presence we can distinguish:- the content, that is, what is present (the intentioned object, noema)- the process, the act of intentioning that content (noesi), which may involve the construction of mental representation.

  28. PHYSICAL INTENTIONAL intentioned content intentioning act (noema) (noesi)

  29. When asked to justify their responses, undergraduates gave reasons which show that their were thinking about: - or the physical object which is the external referent of their imaginative experience - or the intentioned object which is present in their consciousness through the imaginative experience - or the mental process and/or representation which is activated in the imaginative experience and allows to imagine something.

  30. An analogy might be useful to clarify these distinctions. If I see this picture of a pen[] and someone ask me anything about it (for instance: Is it coloured?), I can answer by referring: - or to the physical pen which was the original model reproduced in the picture - or to the pen that I see in the picture (which is a pen with given characteristics - colour, size etc. - but it is not the physical pen; is the physical pen as it is appears in the picture. By looking at the picture, I see the pen but I’m aware that what I see is not a three-dimensional, concrete pen, even though I can imagine to manipulate and so on the pen I see) - or the pattern of pixels activated onto this computer screen, which assumes this given form because of the electronic processes which occur within this machine and which produces electromagnetic waves, and so on

  31. It is worth noticing that references to the third aspect (the mental) were more frequent in the Per-Ima condition: the contrast with the perceptual experience hinted participants at focusing on the mental acts or activities or representational medium involved in the imaginative experience. []

  32. Justification (Questions about the Imagined Pen):Percentages of Each Category under the Two Conditions

  33. Justification (Questions about the Imagined Pen):Comparison between the Two Conditions

  34. Significant associations between yes-no responses and justifications emerged: the expected responses tended to be given by participants who thought of the mental process rather than of the physical or intentioned object. []

  35. Imaginative + Perceptual Condition:Questions about the Imagined Pen Can you lengthen the pen? X2 = 97.94, p < .001 Can another person see the pen? X2 = 73.04, p < .001

  36. Since references to the so-called “mental” aspect of imagery were enhanced by the contrast between the perceptual and the imaginative experiences, we decided to deepen this issue by asking explicitly participants to compare the two experiences (Study 3).

  37. STUDY 3 • Participants were asked to look at a pen (Perceptual situation) and then to create a mental image of that pen (Imaginative situation). • Then they were invited to identify differences between the two situations. • They were also asked 4 questions: • Can you touch the pen? • Can you break the pen? • Can you lengthen the pen? • Can another person see the pen?

  38. Questions were asked with reference both to the perceived pen (“Look at the pen: can you touch it?”) and to the imagined pen (“Try to imagine the pen: can you touch it?”). The order of the two questions within each pair was counterbalanced: 50% of the participants were asked to answer first about the perceived pen and then about the imagined pen(Perceptual + Imaginative condition) the other 50% of the participants were asked to answer first about the imagined pen and then about the perceived pen(Imaginative + Perceptual condition) After each question participants were asked to justify their response.

  39. Responses to the direct hint at realising differences between the perceptual and imaginative situations were classified into the following categories:[] Also in this case it was found that undergraduates made reference to different aspects in order to differentiate the perceptual and the imaginative experiences. Spontaneously, however, they did not identified the “mental” aspects as the differentiating element. We also notice that about 20% of participants failed to find differences between the two situations.

  40. Percentages of “yes-no” responses” were not significantly different in the two conditions, but were higher than those recorded in the previous studies. [] It is likely that the request to detect possible differences between the perceptual and the imaginative situations induced participants to differentiate their responses about the two situations.

  41. Expected Responses to the Questions about the Imagined Pen: Percentages under the Two Conditions

More Related