1 / 137

Arrow’s theorem and the problem of social choice

Arrow’s theorem and the problem of social choice. Can we define the general interest on the basis of individuals interests ?. X , a set of mutually exclusive social states (complete descriptions of all relevant aspects of a society) N a set of individuals N = {1,.., n } indexed by i

Download Presentation

Arrow’s theorem and the problem of social choice

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. Arrow’s theorem and the problem of social choice

  2. Can we define the general interest on the basis of individuals interests ? • X, a set of mutually exclusive social states (complete descriptions of all relevant aspects of a society) • N a set of individuals N = {1,..,n} indexed by i • Ri a preference ordering of individual i on X (with asymmetric and symmetric factors Pi and Ii) • x Ri y means « individual i weakly prefers state x to state y » • Pi = « strict preference », Ii = « indifference » • An ordering is a reflexive, complete and transitive binary relation • The interpretation given to preferences is unclear in Arrow’s work (influenced by economic theory)

  3. Can we define the general interest on the basis of individuals interests ? • <Ri > = (R1 ,…, Rn) a profile of individual preferences •  the set of all binary relations on X •   , the set of all orderings on X • D  n, the set of all admissible profiles • Arrow’s problem: to find a « collective decision rule » C: D   that associates to every profile <Ri > of individual preferences a binary relation R = C(<Ri >) • x R y means that the general interest is (weakly) better served with x than with y when individual preferences are (<Ri >)

  4. Examples of collective decision rules • 1: Dictatorship of individual h: x R y if and only xRhy (not very attractive) • 2: ranking of social states according to an exogenous code (say the Charia). Assume that the exogenous code ranks any pair of social alternatives as per the ordering  (x  y means that x (women can not drive a car) is weakly preferable to y (women drive a car). Then C(<Ri >) =  for all <Ri >  Dis a collective decision rule. Notice that even if everybody in the society thinks that y is strictly preferred to x, the social ranking states that x is better than y.

  5. Examples of collective decision rules • 3: Unanimity rule (Pareto criterion):x R y if and only if xRiy for all individual i. Interesting but deeply incomplete (does not rank alternatives for which individuals preferences conflict) • 4: Majority rule. x R y if and only if #{i N:xRiy}  #{i N :yRix}. Widely used, but does not always lead to a transitive ranking of social states (Condorcet paradox).

  6. the Condorcet paradox

  7. the Condorcet paradox Individual 3 Individual2 Individual1

  8. the Condorcet paradox Individual 3 Individual2 Individual1 Ségolène Nicolas François

  9. the Condorcet paradox Individual 3 Individual2 Individual1 Nicolas François Ségolène Ségolène Nicolas François

  10. the Condorcet paradox Individual 3 Individual2 Individual1 François Ségolène Nicolas Nicolas François Ségolène Ségolène Nicolas François

  11. the Condorcet paradox Individual 3 Individual2 Individual1 François Ségolène Nicolas Nicolas François Ségolène Ségolène Nicolas François A majority (1 and 3) prefers Ségolène to Nicolas

  12. the Condorcet paradox Individual 3 Individual2 Individual1 François Ségolène Nicolas Nicolas François Ségolène Ségolène Nicolas François A majority (1 and 3) prefers Ségolène to Nicolas A majority (1 and 2) prefers Nicolas to François

  13. the Condorcet paradox Individual 3 Individual2 Individual1 François Ségolène Nicolas Nicolas François Ségolène Ségolène Nicolas François A majority (1 and 3) prefers Ségolène to Nicolas A majority (1 and 2) prefers Nicolas to François Transitivity would require that Ségolène be socially preferred to François

  14. the Condorcet paradox Individual 3 Individual2 Individual1 François Ségolène Nicolas Nicolas François Ségolène Ségolène Nicolas François A majority (1 and 3) prefers Ségolène to Nicolas A majority (1 and 2) prefers Nicolas to François Transitivity would require that Ségolène be socially preferred to François but………….

  15. the Condorcet paradox Individual 3 Individual2 Individual1 François Ségolène Nicolas Nicolas François Ségolène Ségolène Nicolas François A majority (1 and 3) prefers Ségolène to Nicolas A majority (1 and 2) prefers Nicolas to François Transitivity would require that Ségolène be socially preferred to François but…………. A majority (2 and 3) prefers strictly François to Ségolène

  16. Example 5: Positional Borda • Works if X is finite. • For every individual i and social state x, define the « Borda score » of x for i as the number of social states that i considers (weakly) worse than x. Borda rule ranks social states on the basis of the sum, over all individuals, of their Borda scores • Let us illustrate this rule through an example

  17. Borda rule Individual 3 Individual2 Individual1 François Ségolène Nicolas Jean-Marie Nicolas François Jean-Marie Ségolène Ségolène Nicolas Jean-Marie François

  18. Borda rule Individual 3 Individual2 Individual1 François 4 Ségolène 3 Nicolas 2 Jean-Marie 1 Nicolas 4 François 3 Jean-Marie 2 Ségolène 1 Ségolène 4 Nicolas 3 Jean-Marie 2 François 1

  19. Borda rule Individual 3 Individual2 Individual1 François 4 Ségolène 3 Nicolas 2 Jean-Marie 1 Nicolas 4 François 3 Jean-Marie 2 Ségolène 1 Ségolène 4 Nicolas 3 Jean-Marie 2 François 1 Sum of scores Ségolène = 8

  20. Borda rule Individual 3 Individual2 Individual1 François 4 Ségolène 3 Nicolas 2 Jean-Marie 1 Nicolas 4 François 3 Jean-Marie 2 Ségolène 1 Ségolène 4 Nicolas 3 Jean-Marie 2 François 1 Sum of scores Ségolène = 8 Sum of scores Nicolas = 9

  21. Borda rule Individual 3 Individual2 Individual1 François 4 Ségolène 3 Nicolas 2 Jean-Marie 1 Nicolas 4 François 3 Jean-Marie 2 Ségolène 1 Ségolène 4 Nicolas 3 Jean-Marie 2 François 1 Sum of scores Ségolène = 8 Sum of scores Nicolas = 9 Sum of scores François = 8

  22. Borda rule Individual 3 Individual2 Individual1 François 4 Ségolène 3 Nicolas 2 Jean-Marie 1 Nicolas 4 François 3 Jean-Marie 2 Ségolène 1 Ségolène 4 Nicolas 3 Jean-Marie 2 François 1 Sum of scores Ségolène = 8 Sum of scores Nicolas = 9 Sum of scores François = 8 Sum of scores Jean-Marie = 5

  23. Borda rule Individual 3 Individual2 Individual1 François 4 Ségolène 3 Nicolas 2 Jean-Marie 1 Nicolas 4 François 3 Jean-Marie 2 Ségolène 1 Ségolène 4 Nicolas 3 Jean-Marie 2 François 1 Sum of scores Ségolène = 8 Sum of scores Nicolas = 9 Sum of scores François = 8 Sum of scores Jean-Marie = 5 Nicolas is the best alternative, followed closely by Ségolène and François. Jean-Marie is the last

  24. Borda rule Individual 3 Individual2 Individual1 François 4 Ségolène 3 Nicolas 2 Jean-Marie 1 Nicolas 4 François 3 Jean-Marie 2 Ségolène 1 Ségolène 4 Nicolas 3 Jean-Marie 2 François 1 Sum of scores Ségolène = 8 Sum of scores Nicolas = 9 Sum of scores François = 8 Sum of scores Jean-Marie = 5 Problem: The social ranking of François, Nicolas and Ségolène depends upon the position of Jean-Marie

  25. Borda rule Individual 3 Individual2 Individual1 François 4 Ségolène 3 Nicolas 2 Jean-Marie 1 Nicolas 4 François 3 Jean-Marie 2 Ségolène 1 Ségolène 4 Nicolas 3 Jean-Marie 2 François 1 Sum of scores Ségolène = 8 Sum of scores Nicolas = 9 Sum of scores François = 8 Sum of scores Jean-Marie = 5 Raising Jean-Marie above Nicolas for 1 and Jean-Marie below Ségolène for 2 changes the social ranking of Ségolène and Nicolas

  26. Borda rule Individual 3 Individual2 Individual1 François 4 Ségolène 3 Nicolas 2 Jean-Marie 1 Nicolas 4 François 3 Jean-Marie 2 Ségolène 1 Ségolène 4 Nicolas 3 Jean-Marie 2 François 1 Sum of scores Ségolène = 8 Sum of scores Nicolas = 9 Sum of scores François = 8 Sum of scores Jean-Marie = 5 Raising Jean-Marie above Nicolas for 1 and Jean-Marie below Ségolène for 2 changes the social ranking of Ségolène and Nicolas

  27. Borda rule Individual 3 Individual2 Individual1 François 4 Ségolène 3 Nicolas 2 Jean-Marie 1 Nicolas 4 François 3 Ségolène 2 Jean-Marie 1 Ségolène 4 Jean-Marie 3 Nicolas 2 François 1 Sum of scores Ségolène = 8 Sum of scores Nicolas = 9 Sum of scores François = 8 Sum of scores Jean-Marie = 5 Raising Jean-Marie above Nicolas for 1 and Jean-Marie below Ségolène for 2 changes the social ranking of Ségolène and Nicolas

  28. Borda rule Individual 3 Individual2 Individual1 François 4 Ségolène 3 Nicolas 2 Jean-Marie 1 Nicolas 4 François 3 Ségolène 2 Jean-Marie 1 Ségolène 4 Jean-Marie 3 Nicolas 2 François 1 Sum of scores Ségolène = 9 Sum of scores Nicolas = 8 Sum of scores François = 8 Sum of scores Jean-Marie = 5 Raising Jean-Marie above Nicolas for 1 and Jean-Marie below Ségolène for 2 changes the social ranking of Ségolène and Nicolas

  29. Borda rule Individual 3 Individual2 Individual1 François 4 Ségolène 3 Nicolas 2 Jean-Marie 1 Nicolas 4 François 3 Ségolène 2 Jean-Marie 1 Ségolène 4 Jean-Marie 3 Nicolas 2 François 1 Sum of scores Ségolène = 9 Sum of scores Nicolas = 8 Sum of scores François = 8 Sum of scores Jean-Marie = 5 Raising Jean-Marie above Nicolas for 1 and Jean-Marie below Ségolène for 2 changes the social ranking of Ségolène and Nicolas

  30. Borda rule Individual 3 Individual2 Individual1 François 4 Ségolène 3 Nicolas 2 Jean-Marie 1 Nicolas 4 François 3 Ségolène 2 Jean-Marie 1 Ségolène 4 Jean-Marie 3 Nicolas 2 François 1 Sum of scores Ségolène = 9 Sum of scores Nicolas = 8 Sum of scores François = 8 Sum of scores Jean-Marie = 5 The social ranking of Ségolène and Nicolas depends on the individual ranking of Nicolas vs Jean-Marie or Ségolène vs Jean-Marie

  31. Are there other collective decision rules ? • Arrow (1951) proposes an axiomatic approach to this problem • He proposes five axioms that, he thought, should be satisfied by any collective decison rule • He shows that there is no rule satisfying all these properties • Famous impossibility theorem, that throw a lot of pessimism on the prospect of obtaining a good definition of general interest as a function of the individual interest

  32. Five desirable properties on the collective decision rule • 1) Non-dictatorship. There exists no individual h in N such that, for all social states x and y, for all profiles <Ri>, x Ph y implies x P y (where R = C(<Ri>) • 2) Collective rationality. The social ranking should always be an ordering (that is, the image of C should be ) (violated by the unanimity and the majority rule; violated also by the Lorenz domination criterion if X is the set of all income distributions) • 3) Unrestricted domain.D =n (all logically conceivable preferences are a priori possible)

  33. Five desirable properties on the collective decision rule • 4) Weak Pareto principle. For all social states x and y, for all profiles <Ri> D , x Pi y for all i Nshould imply x P y (where R = C(<Ri>) (violated by the collective decision rule coming from an exogenous tradition code) • 5) Binary independance from irrelevant alternatives. For every two profiles <Ri> and <R’i> D and every two social states x and y such that xRiy x R’i y for all i, one must have xR y  x R’ y where R = C(<Ri>) and R’ = C(<R’i>). The social ranking of x and y should only depend upon the individual rankings of x and y.

  34. Arrow’s theorem: There does not exist any collective decision function C: D   that satisfies axioms 1-5

  35. Proof of Arrow’s theorem (Sen 1970) • Given two social states x and y and a collective decision function C, say that group of individuals G N is semi-decisive on x and y if and only if x Pi y for all i G and y Ph x for all h  N\G implies x P y (where R = C(<Ri>)) • Analogously, say that group G is decisive on x and y if x Pi y for all i G implies x P y • Clearly, decisiveness on x and y implies semi-decisiveness on that same pair of states. • Strategy of the proof: every collective decision function satisfying axioms 2-5 implies the existence of a decisive individual (a dictator).

  36. Proof of Arrow’s theorem (Sen 1970) • We are going to prove two lemmas. • In the first (field expansion) lemma, we will show that if the collective decision function admits a group G that is semi-decisive on a pair of social states, then this group will in fact be decisive on every pair of states • In the second (groupcontraction) lemma, we are going to use the first lemma to show that if a group G containing at least two individuals is decisive on a pair of social states, then it contains a proper subgroup of individuals that is decisive on that pair. • These two lemmas prove the theorem because, by the Pareto principle, we know that the whole society is decisive on every pair of social states.

  37. Field expansion lemma • Lemma: If C is a collective decision function satisfying axioms 2-5, then, if a group G is semi-decisive on two social states x and y, G is in fact decisive on all social states a and b.

  38. Field expansion lemma • Lemma: If C is a collective decision function satisfying axioms 2-5, then, if a group G is semi-decisive on two social states x and y, G is in fact decisive on all social states a and b. • Proof: We consider several cases.

  39. Field expansion lemma • Lemma: If C is a collective decision function satisfying axioms 2-5, then, if a group G is semi-decisive on two social states x and y, G is in fact decisive on all social states a and b. • Proof: We consider several cases. 1:a = x and b{x,y} .

  40. Field expansion lemma • Lemma: If C is a collective decision function satisfying axioms 2-5, then, if a group G is semi-decisive on two social states x and y, G is in fact decisive on all social states a and b. • Proof: We consider several cases. 1:a = x and b{x,y} . Since C is defined for every preference profile, consider a profile such that x Pi y Pi b for all i in G and y Ph x and y Ph b for all h  N\G.

  41. Field expansion lemma • Lemma: If C is a collective decision function satisfying axioms 2-5, then, if a group G is semi-decisive on two social states x and y, G is in fact decisive on all social states a and b. • Proof: We consider several cases. 1:a = x and b{x,y} . Since C is defined for every preference profile, consider a profile such that x Pi y Pi b for all i in G and y Ph x and y Ph b for all h  N\G. Since G is semi-decisive on x and y, x P y.

  42. Field expansion lemma • Lemma: If C is a collective decision function satisfying axioms 2-5, then, if a group G is semi-decisive on two social states x and y, G is in fact decisive on all social states a and b. • Proof: We consider several cases. 1:a = x and b{x,y} . Since C is defined for every preference profile, consider a profile such that x Pi y Pi b for all i in G and y Ph x and y Ph b for all h  N\G. Since G is semi-decisive on x and y, x P y. Since C satisfies the Pareto principle, y P b and, since the social ranking is transitive, x P b.

  43. Field expansion lemma • Lemma: If C is a collective decision function satisfying axioms 2-5, then, if a group G is semi-decisive on two social states x and y, G is in fact decisive on all social states a and b. • Proof: We consider several cases. 1:a = x and b{x,y} . Since C is defined for every preference profile, consider a profile such that x Pi y Pi b for all i in G and y Ph x and y Ph b for all h  N\G. Since G is semi-decisive on x and y, x P y. Since C satisfies the Pareto principle, y P b and, since the social ranking is transitive, x P b. Now, by binary independence of irrelevant alternatives, the social ranking of x (= a) and b only depends upon the individual preferences over a and b.

  44. Field expansion lemma • Lemma: If C is a collective decision function satisfying axioms 2-5, then, if a group G is semi-decisive on two social states x and y, G is in fact decisive on all social states a and b. • Proof: We consider several cases. 1:a = x and b{x,y} . Since C is defined for every preference profile, consider a profile such that x Pi y Pi b for all i in G and y Ph x and y Ph b for all h  N\G. Since G is semi-decisive on x and y, x P y. Since C satisfies the Pareto principle, y P b and, since the social ranking is transitive, x P b. Now, by binary independence of irrelevant alternatives, the social ranking of x (= a) and b only depends upon the individual preferences over a and b. Yet only the preferences over a and b of the members of G have been specified here.

  45. Field expansion lemma • Lemma: If C is a collective decision function satisfying axioms 2-5, then, if a group G is semi-decisive on two social states x and y, G is in fact decisive on all social states a and b. • Proof: We consider several cases. 1:a = x and b{x,y} . Since C is defined for every preference profile, consider a profile such that x Pi y Pi b for all i in G and y Ph x and y Ph b for all h  N\G. Since G is semi-decisive on x and y, x P y. Since C satisfies the Pareto principle, y P b and, since the social ranking is transitive, x P b. Now, by binary independence of irrelevant alternatives, the social ranking of x (= a) and b only depends upon the individual preferences over a and b. Yet only the preferences over a and b of the members of G have been specified here. Hence G is decisive on a and b.

  46. Field expansion lemma • Lemma: If C is a collective decision function satisfying axioms 2-5, then, if a group G is semi-decisive on two social states x and y, G is in fact decisive on all social states a and b. • Proof: We consider several cases. 2:b = y and a{x,y} .

  47. Field expansion lemma • Lemma: If C is a collective decision function satisfying axioms 2-5, then, if a group G is semi-decisive on two social states x and y, G is in fact decisive on all social states a and b. • Proof: We consider several cases. 2:b = y and a{x,y} . As before, using unrestricted domain, consider a profile such that a Pi x Pi y for all i in G and y Ph x and a Ph x for all h  N\G.

  48. Field expansion lemma • Lemma: If C is a collective decision function satisfying axioms 2-5, then, if a group G is semi-decisive on two social states x and y, G is in fact decisive on all social states a and b. • Proof: We consider several cases. 2:b = y and a{x,y} . As before, using unrestricted domain, consider a profile such that a Pi x Pi y for all i in G and y Ph x and a Ph x for all h  N\G. Since G is semi-decisive on x and y, one has x P y.

  49. Field expansion lemma • Lemma: If C is a collective decision function satisfying axioms 2-5, then, if a group G is semi-decisive on two social states x and y, G is in fact decisive on all social states a and b. • Proof: We consider several cases. 2:b = y and a{x,y} . As before, using unrestricted domain, consider a profile such that a Pi x Pi y for all i in G and y Ph x and a Ph x for all h  N\G. Since G is semi-decisive on x and y, one has x P y. Since C satisfies the Pareto principle, a P x and, since the social ranking is transitive, a P y.

  50. Field expansion lemma • Lemma: If C is a collective decision function satisfying axioms 2-5, then, if a group G is semi-decisive on two social states x and y, G is in fact decisive on all social states a and b. • Proof: We consider several cases. 2:b = y and a{x,y} . As before, using unrestricted domain, consider a profile such that a Pi x Pi y for all i in G and y Ph x and a Ph x for all h  N\G. Since G is semi-decisive on x and y, one has x P y. Since C satisfies the Pareto principle, a P x and, since the social ranking is transitive, a P y. Now, by binary independence of irrelevant alternatives, the social ranking of a and b (= y) only depends upon the individual preferences over a and b.

More Related