1 / 22

Ethics and Religion

Ethics and Religion. Why is God necessary for there to be a universal moral law? A universal moral law needs an adequate foundation. Why, someone might ask, is it that only God can serve as an adequate foundation for a universal moral law?

sai
Download Presentation

Ethics and Religion

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. Ethics and Religion • Why is God necessary for there to be a universal moral law? • A universal moral law needs an adequate foundation. • Why, someone might ask, is it that only God can serve as an adequate foundation for a universal moral law? • Isn’t there, asks the critic, any other possibly adequate foundation?

  2. Could evolution provide an adequate foundation? • Universal moral law as “herd instinct.” • “The position of the modern evolutionist . . . is that humans have an awareness of morality . . . because such an awareness is of biological worth. Morality is a biological adaptation no less than are hands and feet and teeth . . . . Morality is just an aid to survival and reproduction, . . . and any deeper meaning is illusory . . . .” Michael Ruse, “Evolutionary Theory and Christian Ethics”

  3. Ruse, however, also claims “[t]he man who says that it is morally acceptable to rape little children is just as mistaken as the man who says 2+2=3.” Michael Ruse, Darwinism Defended • But, how can this be, if universal moral law is nothing more than a herd instinct? • In other words, can any being endowed with thought and choice be absolutely bound by a herd instinct?

  4. To illustrate why the answer is “No,” philosopher John Hick asks us to imagine an ant suddenly endowed with thought and choice: • “Suppose [the ant] to be called upon to immolate himself for the sake of the ant-hill. He feels the powerful pressure of instinct pushing him towards this self-destruction. But, he asks himself why he should voluntarily . . . carry out

  5. “the suicidal programme to which instinct prompts him? Why should he regard the future existence of a million million other ants as more important to him than his own continued existence . . . ? [S]urely, in so far as he is free from the domination of the blind force of instinct, he will opt [and should opt] for life – his own life.” John Hick, Arguments for the Existence of God

  6. Defenders of the Divine Command Theory claim that a universal moral law requires a Lawgiver who is superior, in every way, to those who are bound by it. • “A duty is something that is owed . . . . But, something can be owed only to some person or persons. There can be no such thing as duty in isolation . . . . The idea of political or legal obligation is clear enough . . . . Similarly, the idea of an obligation higher than this,

  7. “and referred to as moral obligation, is clear enough, provided reference to some lawmaker higher . . . . than those of the state is understood. In other words, our moral obligations can . . . be understood as those that are imposed by God. This does give a clear sense to the claim that our moral obligations are more binding upon us than our political obligations . . . . But, what if this higher-than-human lawgiver is

  8. “no longer taken into account? Does the concept of a moral obligation . . . still make sense . . . ? [T]he concept of moral obligation [is] unintelligible apart form the idea of God. The words remain, but their meaning is gone.” Richard Taylor, Ethics, Faith, and Reason • Famous atheists concede that universal moral law requires that God be the Lawgiver.

  9. “[I]t is very distressing that God does not exist, because all possibility of finding values in a Heaven of ideas disappears along with Him . . . . [A]s a result, man is forlorn, because neither within him nor without does he find anything to cling to . . . . If God does not exist, we find no values or commands to turn to which legitimize our conduct.” Jean Paul Sartre, “Existentialism”

  10. As the quote indicates, since he believed that an objective morality can be grounded only in God and since he also believed God does not exist, Sartre believed that human life is absurd and meaningless. • This is why he said man is forlorn.

  11. One can ask: Does the Lawgiver who stands the behind the universal moral have to be the maximally perfect God of Classical Theism? • Perhaps not, but clearly he would have to be very similar. • To construct a law universally binding on all humans, the Lawgiver would clearly have to be very wise and very good.

  12. Also, the matter of the ultimate enforcement of the universal moral law suggests the Lawgiver must be very powerful. • Defenders of the Divine Command Theory maintain that it makes sense to claim humans are absolutely bound to obey the universal moral law, only if, ultimately, everyone gets his/her just desserts.

  13. “[Immanuel] Kant . . . builds his argument for the existence of God on . . . the observed disparity between moral worthiness and the possession of happiness. If the universe is a truly moral place, then God must exist as an omnipotent Being capable of ensuring a just relation (if not in this world, then in the next) between moral worthiness and the attainment of its reward.” Ed. L. Miller, God and Reason: An Invitation to Philosophical Theology, p. 92

  14. As Miller indicates, Kant, along with the other defenders of the Divine Command Theory, maintain that the universal moral law requires not only the existence of God but also the existence of an afterlife. • It is clear that not everyone gets his/her just deserts in this life. • But, for it to make sense that there is a universal moral law, ultimately, everyone must get his/her just desserts.

  15. Thus, there must be a life after this one in which everyone does get his/her just desserts. • “If there is no immortality, then all things are permitted.” Fyodor Dostoyevsky, The Brothers Karmazov • It’s not, say the defenders of the Divine Command Theory, that you can’t trust people to do the right thing when they have no fear of Hell.

  16. It’s that it does not make any sense to do anything other than exactly what you want to do, if you never have to account for what you do. • “Somebody might say that it is in our best self-interest to adopt a moral life-style. But, clearly, that is not always true: We all know situations in which self-interest runs smack in the face of morality. Moreover, if one is sufficiently powerful,

  17. “like a Ferdinand Marcos or a Papa Doc Duvalier or even a Donald Trump, then one can pretty much ignore the dictates of conscience and safely live in self-indulgence.” William Lane Craig, “The Indispensability of Theological Meta-Ethical Foundations for Morality” • “[If there is no afterlife or God,] [t]here is no objective reason why man should be moral, unless morality ‘pays off’

  18. “in his social life or makes him ‘feel good.’ There is no objective reason why man should do anything save for the pleasure it affords him.” Stewart C. Easton, The Western Heritage • A critic of the Divine Command Theory might raise the Euthyphro problem. • The problem was first raise by Plato in his dialogue The Euthyphro.

  19. To wit: Is something good because God wills it, or does God will something because it is good? • Neither possibility is appealing. • If the first possibility is correct, then the universal moral law is totally arbitrary. • If the second possibility is correct, then God really isn’t the ground of the universal moral law because there is something beyond even Him by which He is bound.

  20. Response to the Euthyphro Problem • “God’s own holy and perfectly good nature supplies the absolute standard against which all actions and decisions are measured . . . . He is the locus and source of moral value. He is by nature loving, generous, just, faithful, kind, and so forth. Moreover, God’s moral nature is expressed in relation to us

  21. “in the form of divine commands which constitute our moral duties or obligations. Far from being arbitrary, these commands flow necessarily from His moral nature . . . . On this foundation we can affirm the objective goodness and rightness of love, generosity, self-sacrifice, and equality, and condemn as objectively evil and wrong selfishness, hatred, abuse, discrimination, and oppression.” William Lane Craig, “The Indispensability of Theological Meta-Ethical Foundations for Morality”

  22. Final Thought • “If God does not exist, then it is plausible to think that there are no objective moral values, that we have no moral duties, and that there is no moral accountability for how we live and act. The horror of such a morally neutral world is obvious. If . . . we hold, as it seems rational to do, that objective moral values and duties do exist, then we have good [if not conclusive] grounds for believing in the existence of God.” William Lane Craig, “The Indispensability of Theological Meta-Ethical Foundations for Morality”

More Related