1 / 16

14.127BehavioralEconomics. Lecture 9

14.127BehavioralEconomics. Lecture 9. Xavier Gabaix April8, 2004. 1 SelfControlProblems. 1.1 Hyperbolic discounting Do you want a small cookie us now ( t 0 =0)or a big cookie u b later ( t 1 =1 week)? Many people prefer ( u s ,0)to ( u b , t 1 ).

suki
Download Presentation

14.127BehavioralEconomics. Lecture 9

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. 14.127BehavioralEconomics. Lecture 9 Xavier Gabaix April8, 2004

  2. 1 SelfControlProblems 1.1 Hyperbolic discounting Do you want a small cookie us now (t0=0)or a big cookie ub later (t1=1 week)? Many people prefer (us,0)to (ub,t1)

  3. Denote by Δ(t)the discount factor applied to time t Then At the same time many people prefer (us,t)to (ub,t+t1)where t=1 year, and t1= 1day. Thus,

  4. Denote and note ψ(t)>ψ(0) Thus is increasing.

  5. Let us write Then Standard exponential modal Empirical evidence points to decreasing In comparison of today and tomorrow emotions are silent, in comparison of 1000 days from now and 1001days cognition takes over.

  6. Maybe people compare ratios: 1 in t=1000 days vs Xt in t+1 =1001 days. For indifference something like is plausible. for large t. Clearly Xt → 1 as t → ∞. But, Thus Xt→ 1 iff If X(t)= Thus for large t.

  7. Thus Postulate That’s why this is called hyperbolic discounting

  8. Quasihyperbolic approximation (Phelps and Pollack 1968, Laibson 1997) Typically, β≤1. Now, This function is tractable. It does not get Xt→1 though.

  9. 1.2 Open question What is t =1 ? For cookie it might be 1 hour. For small money it might be 1 week. For macro consumption it is one quarter. Empirically, δ≃. 98is yearly units, and β≃ 6 is usually found for all time units. What detemines β? Clearly, the appeal of the good seems to matter. A nice, moist cookie may have a lower β,while a fairly stable plain bagel may have a β close to1.

  10. 1.3 Dynamic inconsistency Example. Do the task (taxes) at t∈{0,1,2} at a cost c0 =1, c1=1.5,C2 = 2.5. Takeβ= and δ=1. Take Self 0 (the decision maker at time 0). Disutility of doing the task at 0 is 1, at 1 is , at time 2 is 1.25. So, Self 0 would to the task to 4 be done at t=1. Self 1 compares time 1 cost of 1.5with time 2 cost of 1.25and prefers the task to be done at time 2. Self 2 does the task at the cost 2.5.

  11. Proposition. If the decision criterion at t is max the there is dynamic inconsistency unless there exists a constant ηsuch that Δ(s)= Δ(0)ηt. Proof (sketch). Take t =0 and choose c0. Self 0 planned c1,c2,…maximizes max over c1,c2,… satysfying a budget constraint. Self 1 maximizes max subject to the same budget constaraint For the choices to be the same, there must be a constant ηs.t. ,which implies

  12. 1.4 Naives vs sophisticates. Sophisticates understand the structure of the game and use backward induction. — In the example above a sophisticate understands that time 1 Self is not going to do the taxes and time 2 Self is going to do them, unless Self 0 does. So Self 0 chooses to do his taxes. — But the first best would be to force Self 1 to do the taxes. — You don’t see too much commitment schemes in pratice. — Maybe they will be developed by the market, or maybe all consumers are naives.

  13. • Naive thinks that future selfs will act according to his wishes. — Naives don’t want commitment devices. • Are people naives or sophisticates? — We see some commitment devices, e.g. mortgage is forced savings. Partial naives (O’Donoghue and Rabin, Doing it now or later, AER 1999) — Self t’s preferences are (1, )but Self t thinks that future selves have (1, ) — If =βthen the agent is sophisticated. If =1then the agent is naive.

  14. 1.5 Paradoxes with sophisticated hyperbolics Sophisticated hyperbolics have consumption that is a nonmonotonic function of their wealth if there are borrowing constraints (Harris and Laibson,“Dynamic Choices of Hyperbolic Consumers”, Econometrica 2004) This pushes very far the assumption of sophistication. That disappears if the environment is noisy enough (that smoothes out the ups and downs)

  15. 1.6 Continuous time hyperbolics Harris and Laibson: “Instantaneous gratification”. Agents maximize where Δ(t)equals Δ(t−dt)(1−ρdt)with probability 1−λdtand equals βΔ(t−dt)with probability λdt. They have only one shock in a lifetime. So:

  16. where T is a Poisson(λ)arrival time. One can do continuous time Bellman Equations. Nice paper by Luttmer and Mariotti (JPE 2003).

More Related