1 / 49

TM, DTM, NP, NPC, BB(n) C(L, t), reducibility

TM, DTM, NP, NPC, BB(n) C(L, t), reducibility. Advanced Algorithms By Me Dr. Mustafa Sakalli March, 19, 2012. Halting Problem Superpolynomial time algorithms Easy and hard problems Some interesting problems Shortest vs. longest simple paths Euler tour vs. hamiltonian cycle

teness
Download Presentation

TM, DTM, NP, NPC, BB(n) C(L, t), reducibility

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. TM, DTM, NP, NPC, BB(n)C(L, t), reducibility Advanced Algorithms By Me Dr. Mustafa Sakalli March, 19, 2012.

  2. Halting Problem • Superpolynomial time algorithms • Easy and hard problems • Some interesting problems Shortest vs. longest simple paths Euler tour vs. hamiltonian cycle 2-CNF satisfiability vs. 3-CNF satisfiability • The classes P and NP and NP-completeness Class P, Polynomial-time algorithms:problems that are solvable in polynomial time.On inputs of size n, the worst-case running time is O(nk) for some constant k. Class NP: those problems that are "verifiable" in polynomial time. Class NPC: those problems that are in NP and are as "hard" as any problem in NP.

  3. Introduction • Computational problems for which • fast algorithms have never been found, • but neither have such algorithms been proved to be unattainable. • Examples: • The primality-testing problem, for which the best-known algorithm on the brink of polynomial time, and • The integer-factoring problem, for which the known algorithms in a more primitive condition. • Many such problems, not just a list of seemingly difficult computational problems, in fact bound together by strong structural ties. Called the NP-complete problems: • The traveling salesman problem (‘TSP’): Given n points in the plane (‘cities’), and a distance D. Queston: Is there a tour that visits all n of the cities, returns to its starting point, and has total length D? • Graph coloring: Given a graph G and an integer K. Can the vertices be properly colored in K of colors? Knsuch possibilities, n the number of the vertices. • Independent set: Given a graph G and an integer K. Is there a V(G) containing an independent set of K vertices?

  4. Introduction • Bin packing: Given a finite set S of positive integers, and an integer N (the number of bins). Does there • exist a partition of S into N or fewer subsets such that the sum of the integers in each subset is K? In • other words, ‘pack’ the integers of S into at most N bins with the capacity K? • These are hard problems, but there can be easy instances, ie if the graph G happens to have no edges at all, or a very few of them, then it will be very easy to figure out a possible coloring, or determine the presence of an independent set of K vertices. • Suppose a manufacturer gives a warranty of the worst case performance for independent set, nK…ie 1000n8… Adjacency matrix dimension n, the element number would be n2, hence the input size B=n1/2. B bits. Time T=BK/2, which is polynomial if K would have been fixed. But our focus is all the instances of the independent set problem.

  5. Some properties of the NP-complete problems • The problems computationally very difficult, for any of which no polynomial time algorithms have been found. Which means If a fast algorithm could be found for one of which then there would be fast algorithms for all of them. • But not any proof given yet indicating that polynomial time algorithms for these problems do not exist. Similarly, if it could be proved that no fast algorithm exists for one of the NP-complete problems, then there could not be a fast algorithm for any other of those problems. • "The question of the existence or nonexistence of polynomial-time algorithms for the NP-complete problems probably rates as the principal unsolved problem that faces theoretical computer science today.“ Page: 105.

  6. Our next task will be to develop the formal machinery that will permit us to give precise definitions of all of the concepts that are needed. In the remainder of this section we will discuss the additional ideas informally, and then in section 5.2 we’ll state them quite precisely.

  7. Decision problems vs. optimization problems Optimization problems, find the feasible solution with the best value. Decision problems, verifying the membership with the answer of "yes" or "no" • Casting an optimization problem into a related decision problem – by imposing a bound on the value of it, to be optimized. –complexity of optimization problem is equal to complexity of related decision problem. – Shortest path: does there exist a path from vertex u to v of length at most k? Reductions A procedure that transforms any instance α of decision problem A into some instance β of decision problem B with the characteristics: 1 The transformation takes polynomial time. 2 The answers are the same. That is, the answer for α is "yes" if and only if the answer for β is also "yes." A string of an Instance: for a particular problem Algorithm for the reduction, Polynomial-time reduction algorithm:

  8. Idea behind a decision and optimization problems • Many of the problems can be phrased as decision problems or as optimization problems. • A decision problem is one that asks only for a yes-or-no answer: • Can this graph be 5-colored? • Is there a tour of length  15 miles? • Is there a set of 67 independent vertices? • An optimization problem is one that asks the value that provides on of the feasible solution. • What is the smallest number of colors with which G can be colored? • What is the length of the shortest tour of these cities? • What is the size of the largest independent set of vertices in G? • Usually if we find a fast algorithm for a decision problem then with just a little more work we will be able to merge it, to solve the corresponding optimization problem.

  9. Idea behind a decision and optimization problems • Example: suppose we have an algorithm that solves the decision problem for graph coloring, and what we want is the solution of the optimization problem (the chromatic number). • A G of 100 vertices, Q: Can the graph be 50-colored? • If so, then the 1 cr  50. Split the range by 2 for every run, and keep on asking the question? Yes for second half, and no for the first half. • After O(log n) steps we will have found the cr. Hence if there is a fast way to do the decision problem then there is a fast way to do the optimization problem. The converse is true or obvious. Linear Optimization, Simplex, Ellipsoidal so on. • Our Attention is on Decision Problems.

  10. What is a language and the class P, and class NP? • Decision problem asking: Question: If a given word (the input string) does or does not belong to a certain language. The language is the totality of words for which the answer is ‘Y.’ • The graph 3-coloring language. Question: Does the vertex adjacency matrix of a graph represent, if it is 3-colorable. A 3-colorability computation is therefore nothing but an attempt to discover whether a given word belongs to the dictionary. • What is the class P? • We say that a decision problem belongs to the class P if there is an algorithm Aand a number csuch that for every instance Iof the problem the algorithm Awill produce a solution in time O(Bc), • Briefly, P is the set of easy decision problems. Examples: Determining • Relative primality of given two integers. • Divisibility of an integer by another. • K=2 colorablity of a G. • A flow of value greater than K in a network. • K - connectedness of a G.If a G be disconnected by the removal of K or fewer edges. • A matching of K – or more edges in a bipartite G.

  11. What is a language and the class P, and class NP? • What is the class P? • We say that a decision problem belongs to the class P if there is an algorithm Aand a number csuch that for every instance Iof the problem the algorithm Awill produce a solution in time O(Bc), • Briefly, P is the set of easy decision problems. Examples: Determining • Relative primality of given two integers. • Divisibility of an integer by another. • K=2 colorablity of a G. • A flow of value greater than K in a network. • K - connectedness of a G.If a G be disconnected by the removal of K or fewer edges. • A matching of K – or more edges in a bipartite G.

  12. NP is a class of Decision Problems for which it is easy to check the correctness of a claimed answer. Not addressing to find a solution, but only verifying that an alleged solution is correct. • A decision problem Q belongs to NP if there is an algorithm A that does the following: • Associated with each word of the language Q (i.e.,with each instance I for which the answer is ‘Yes’) there is a certificate C(I) such that when the pair (I,C(I)) are input to algorithm A it recognizes that I belongs to the language Q. • If I is some word that does not belong to the language Q then there is no choice of certificate C(I) that will cause A to recognize I as a member of Q. • Algorithm A operates in polynomial time. Verifiable • An analogy of the distinction between the classes of P and NP. • Reading through a difficult proof of some mathematical theorem, and verifying its correctness, which is much easier than going through the invention of the idea as it happened. • Some proofs are extremely time consuming even to check (the proof of the 4-color theorem!), and some computational problems are not even known to belong to NP, let alone to P. • The problems in class P are the problems easy to find a solution, and those in NP are the problems where it’s easy to check a solution that may have been very tedious to find.

  13. Consider the graph coloring problem to be the decision problem Q. Certainly the graph coloring problem is not known to be in P. However, in NP. • A hard method of constructing certificates that proves it. • Suppose G is some graph K-colorable. • The certificate of G is a list of the colors assigned to each vertex in some proper K-coloring of the vertices. • How to produce that list? • Not easy to construct a certificate. One needs to solve a hard problem for every entry of G. DP memoization?. • Then checking the correctness of an alleged answer is • either show that the color of each vertex is assigned a proper color of K-coloring, • or go to hard path to provide a certificate, and only check first that every vertex has only one color (as listed) and check that no more than K colors have been used altogether, and finally check that every edge e of G is terminated by two different colors. All checking takes a polynomial time, and hence the graph coloring problem belongs to NP.

  14. For the tsp, suppose we produce a certificate that contains a tour, whose total length isK. • The checking algorithm Awould then verify that the tour really does visit all of the cities and really does have total length K. without seeking all possible K solutions through each of the vertices. Polynomial. • The TSP, therefore, also belongs to NP. • How could a problem fail to belong to NP?’ • Try this decision problem: an instance I of a G with ncities and a positive number K. • The question is ‘Is it true that there is not a tour of all of these cities whose total length is less than K?’ This is a kind of a negation of the tsp. • Does the negated TSP belong to NP? If so, there must be an algorithm Aand a way of making a certificate C(I) for each instance I so that absence of such a tour can be verified. Any certificate or even any algorithm to generate C is known yet. Therefore, not known if this negation of the tsp belongs to NP.

  15. Problems belong to NP but not immediately obvious? Pratt’s algorithm is a method of producing a certificate with a quick check that a given integer is prime. • The decision problem ‘Given n, is it prime?’ is thereby revealed to belong to NP, although that fact wasn’t obvious at a glance. • 1903 a speaker announced in a math convention that 267 - 1 = multiplication of two long prime numbers. Listeners must work this one out, polynomial checking A the claimed result, and determining yes or no. • But in fact if one needs work very hard to find these numbers. • Verifying compositeness of n, Certification C(n), r 1, s 1, n = rs. • Checking algorithm for a pair of primes, verify that • r 1, s 1 • n = rs.

  16. The hard part is to convince an audience that "a certain integer n is a prime number”. • The rules: Allowed to do any immense amount of calculation beforehand, and the • results can be listed on a certificate C(n) that accompanies the integer n. However, the audience, will need to do only a polynomial amount of computation in order to convince themselves that n is prime. Or accept the fact. A primality-checking algorithm Awith the following properties: • A ( n, C(n)): Inputs to Aare the integer nand a certain certificate C(n). • If nis prime then Afor the given inputs (n, C(n)) results on the output ‘n is prime.’ • If nis not prime then for every possible certificate C(n) the action of Aon the inputs (n, C(n)) results in the output ‘primality of n is not verified.’ • Algorithm A runs in polynomial time. Now the question is, does such a procedure exist for primality verification? The answer is affirmative. Every prime number has a succinct certificate 1975, Pratt. This has a great importance for the developments of NPC. • The next lemma is a kind of converse to ‘Fermat’s little theorem’.

  17. Fermat’s little theorem. • Lemma. Let p be a positive integer. Suppose there is an integer x such that xp−1 =1 (mod p) and such that for all divisors d of (p − 1), d < (p − 1), we have xd1 (mod p). Then p is prime. • Proof: gcd(x, p) = 1, and suppose g = gcd(x, p). Then x = gg', p = gg''. • Since xp−1 =1(mod p) we have xp−1 = 1+tp and (gg')(p−1)− tgg'' = 1. The left side is a multiple of g. The right side is not, unless g = 1.

  18. Fermat’s little theorem. • Lemma. Let p be a positive integer. Suppose there is an integer x such that xp−1 =1 (mod p) and such that for all divisors d of (p − 1), d < (p − 1), we have xd1 (mod p). Then p is prime. • Proof: p | np − n • Case: Let p | n, then, obviously, p | np − n, and we are done. • Case p ¬| n. • Consider n, 2n, 3n, . . . , (p − 1)n • By the Division Algorithm we have • n = p k1 + r1, p | n - r1, • …, • (p-1)n = p k(p-1) + r(p-1), p | (p-1)n - r(p-1), • 0<r(p-1)p-1 • r(p-1)0, since otherwise p | i n, therefore p | i, orp | n, • Let a, b, c, d, and p be integers such that • p | (a − b) and p | (c − d). • Then p | (ac − bd). • p | [(p − 1)! np−1 − (p − 1)!]. • p | (p − 1)! (np−1 − 1). • p ¬| (p − 1)!, then p | (np−1 − 1).

  19. For the tsp, suppose we produce a certificate that contains a tour, whose total length isK. • The checking algorithm Awould then verify that the tour really does visit all of the cities and really does have total length K. without seeking all possible K solutions through each of vertices. • The TSP, therefore, also belongs to NP. • How could a problem fail to belong to NP?’ • Try this decision problem: an instance I of a G with ncities and a positive number K. • The question is ‘Is it true that there is not a tour of all of these cities whose total length is less than K?’ This is a kind of a negation of the tsp. • Does the negated TSP belong to NP? If so, there must be an algorithm Aand a way of making a certificate C(I) for each instance I so that absence of such a tour can be verified. Any certificate or even any algorithm to generate C is known yet. Therefore, not known if this negation of the tsp belongs to NP. • Problems belong to NP but not immediately obvious? Pratt’s algorithm is a method of producing a certificate with a quick check that a given integer is prime. • The decision problem ‘Given n, is it prime?’ is thereby revealed to belong to NP, although that fact wasn’t obvious at a glance. • It is very clear that PNP. Indeed if Q  P is some decision problem then we can verify membership in the language Q with the empty certificate. That is, we don’t even need a certificate in order to do a quick calculation that checks membership in the language because the problem itself can be quickly solved. • It seems natural to suppose that NP is larger than P. That is, one might presume that there are problems • whose solutions can be quickly checked with the aid of a certificate even though they can’t be quickly found • in the first place. • No example of such a problem has ever been produced (and proved), nor has it been proved that no • such problem exists. The question of whether or not P=NP is the one that we cited earlier as being perhaps • the most important open question in the subject area today. • It is fairly obvious that the class P is called ‘the class P’ because ‘P’ is the first letter of ‘Polynomial • Time.’ But what does ‘NP’ stand for? Stay tuned. The answer will appear in section 5.2.

  20. Whereevery I travel this world, epics lyrics.

  21. Uncountable SET-not enumerable • A set is uncountable if its cardinal number is larger than that of the set of all cardinal numbers. • Its characterization iff any holds.. • No injective correspondence (f) from X to the set of natural numbers. • X is nonempty and there is surjective function from the set of natural numbers to X. • The cardinality of X is neither finite nor equal to the cardinality of natural numbers!! • The cardinality of X is strictly grater than cardinality of natural number. • If cardinality of subset of a set Y is infinite, than set Y is uncountable. • Cantor’s diagonal argument. • Uncountable sets • R, the cardinality of R (c or 2N0, ]1 - beth-one) is called cardinality of the continuum. ]2 beth-two cardinality of more uncountable numbers. • Cantor set that is an uncountable subset of R and has Hausdorff dimension number between 0 and 1. (Fact: Any subset of R of Hausdorff dimension greater than 0 must be uncountable). • Earlier Cantor poses question if ]1 = N1 (aleph1), cardinality of ordinal numbers, • First in the list of Hilbert’s 23 questions, 1900.

  22. Schubfachprinzip drawer principle • n pigeons > m nests. 10 to 9, at least one nest must be shared. At least one box must contain no fewer than ceiling(n/m), and at least one box must contain no more than floor(n/m). • Collision probability with a uniform probability of 1/m is equal to • 1-{m(m-1)..(m-n+1)}/mn • If the cardinality of set A is greater than those of set B, then there is NO injection from A to B.

  23. Numbers that cannot be counted cannot be computed, but infinite c programs can be counted. • static void Main() 1/7.. • { Console.Write("0."); while (true) Console.Write("142857"); • } • Pi • …

  24. Cantor’s Diagonal Argument Let T be a set of consisting all infinite sequences, and its permutations of S=f(i). • Characteristic function of sequence is a function f(i)=1. • If X has characteristic function f, then its complement is 1-f(i). Sequence S is countable since possible to associate only one number n of N for every element of the sequence S. And T is countable.. • s1 = {1…..0 ….},  f1(i) mapping f(i) • s2 = {……., ….},  f2(i) • s3 = • .. • Thus new s is not in   {s1, s2, s3, ...}. This contradicts the assumption that the list has contained all the sequences.

  25. Cantor’s Diagonal Argument • All the possible countable numbers must be included in the set, but always possible to obtain another s0=cmplt{diag(T)}=cmplt(fn(n))=cmplt(sn,n), which is s0 T. Cmplt referes complement of. • Therefore T is uncountable, since if S0. included in, there will be another one which cannot be placed in one-to-one correspondence with the set of N. • There is no bijection between N and T, but T may be subcountable. • Although both sets are infinite in conclusion there are more infinite sequences of real numbers than that could be mapped with natural numbers.

  26. Cantor’s Diagonal Argument • Some function will not yield bijection condition, f(t)=0.t, check if t=1000.. And its cmpt(t).. Two different sequences corresponds to one number. But possible to modify function and avoid this situation that takes us to.. I am not sure how to prove, but it says that R and T have the same cardinality which is called generalized cardinality of continuum which is also given as cardinality between |S| and |P(s)|. Cardinality between integers and reals is called continuum hypothesis.

  27. Inconsistency of notions. • P(S) is the Power of a set, defined as all the subsets of S. Cantor’s theorem states that cardinality of P(S) is larger then those of S. • Suppose f is a function from S to P(S), • T={s  S: sf(s)}, second statement is from Cantor’s diagonalization. Either s is in T (by the definition, from the same definition f(s)T, then |T|+|f(s)||P(s)|) or if s is not in T, which is a violation of the definition, but also and |T|+|s||P(s)|. • Inconsistency of “set of all sets that do not contain themsleves in the set”. • If S were the set of all sets, then P(S) would be bigger than {S and a subset of S}. • Similar to Russell's Paradox, based on an unrestricted comprehension scheme, is contradictory. • Russell’s Paradox if let   D = {x|x not in x}.     Then D in D   iff   D not in D,  a contradiction. • For example, the conventional proof of the unsolvability of the halting problem is essentially a diagonal argument of Cantors arg. • Also, diagonalization was originally used to show the existence of arbitrarily hard complexity classes and played a key role in early attempts to prove P does not equal NP. In 2008, diagonalization was used to "slam the door" on Laplace's demon.1

  28. Russell's paradox • The set M is the set of all sets that do not contain themselves as members. Does M contain itself? • If it does, it is not a member of M according to the definition. If it does not, then it has to be a member of M, again according to the definition of M. Therefore, both of the statements "M is a member of M " and "M is not a member of M " lead to contradictions.For example: • "A is an element of M if and only if A is not an element of A". • M = {s  S| sf(s)}, or M = {x|xx}. • 1) List of all lists that do not contain themselves.If the "List of all lists that do not contain themselves" contains itself, then it does not belong to itself and should be removed. However, if it does not list itself, then it should be added to itself.2) Barber paradoxThe paradox considers a town with a male barber who shaves all and only those men who do not shave themselves.

  29. Function x  x < 2 is the set of all numbers less than 2. Set membership is via application: e member-of S iff S(e) is true. Since (Function x  x < 2)(1) is true, 1 is in this "set". Now consider P = "the set of all sets that do not contain themselves as members"!: P = Function x  Not(x)(x) (Note, it may make sense to have a set with itself as member: the set {{{{...}}}}, infinitely receding, has itself as a member; this only happens in so-called non-well-founded set theory).

  30. Now, is P P? Namely is P a member of itself? This is written: (function x  not(x x)) (function x  not(x x)) --if this were viewed as a D program, it would loop forever: Compute Not((Function x  Not(x x))(Function x  Not(x x)))) Now, notice we have P is a member of itself if and only if it isn't, a contradiction! The computational realization of the paradox is that the predicate cannot compute to true or false, so its not a sensible logical statement. To avoid this problem, Russell developed his theory of types.

  31. Avoiding Russell's paradox: type theory and axiomatic set theory • Old classic set of self-referential paradoxical statements causing ambiguities that are neither true nor false could be avoided. • In mathematical terms. the set of all sets that are members of the themselves, permitting self-referential sets, allowing the set of all sets that contain themselves as a member. • But the set of all sets that do not contain themselves as a member? are they a member of themselves. • To avoid paradox, Russell with Whitehead propose a type theory, in which sentences were arranged hierarchically. • This definition avoids the paradox: the definition of R must now define R as a set of type k set containing all sets of type k − 1 and below that do not contain themselves as members. Since R is a type k set, it cannot contain itself, since it cannot contain any type k sets. This avoids the possibility of having to talk about “the set of all sets that are not members of themselves”, because the two parts of the sentence are of different types - that is, at different levels.

  32. Avoiding Russell's paradox: type theory and axiomatic set theory • This definition avoids the paradox: the definition of R must now define R as a set of type k set containing all sets of type k − 1 and below that do not contain themselves as members. Since R is a type k set, it cannot contain itself, since it cannot contain any type k sets. This avoids the possibility of having to talk about “the set of all sets that are not members of themselves”, because the two parts of the sentence are of different types - that is, at different levels. • Another approach to avoid such types of paradoxes was an axiomatic set theory, proposed by Ernst Zermelo. This theory determines what operations were allowed and when.

  33. Some Logics used in axiomatizations of mathematics • A logic usually refers to a set of rules about constructing valid sentences. Here are a few logics. Propositional logic concerns sentences such as (p ¬q)  (¬p  r) where p, q, r are boolean variables. Recall that the SAT problem consists of determining the satisfiability of such sentences. In first order logic, the symbols allowed are relation and function symbols as well as quantification symbols  and . For instance, the statement xS(x) x is a first order sentence in which x is quantified universally, S() is a unary relation symbol and  is a binary relation. Finally, second order logic allows sentences in which one is allowed quantification over structures, i.e., functions and relations. An example of a second order sentence is SxS(x)  x, where S is a unary relation symbol.

  34. Corollary: There are uncountably many subsets of N. D:\godel.html • Hence one must accept that not possible to comprehend the list of comprehensible sequences.   • The same applies to "sequences which God can comprehend".   Thus omniscience has some limits.

  35. Godel showed that a formal system that is both complete and consistent could not be created since he proved that any formal system which is complete cannot be prevented from including self-referential statements. The way that happens is through something called models - a formal system is only valid if there is a model which fits its system of rules. If a system is capable of being represented by a model which is complete, then it is also capable of being represented by a model which encodes self-referential statements, and thus comes the self referential paradox. Alan Turing and others were interested in with a mechanical perfect complete computing device. If such a system exists, then one can use a computer program with the rules of that system to enumerate every true statement - or can write a program which can take any statement as input, and tell whether or not that statement is true. REDUCTION. Which was something not possible as proved by Godel. But Turing and others found an easier way to prove its impossibility: the halting problem.

  36. The halting problem considers a simple question: Write a program which looks at any arbitrary computer programs, and determines whether or not any other prg will eventually stop when it is run for some input. Computing system S(p,i), which computes a function with a pair of inputs that are a program p, and an input i for that program of p, then, we are writing a program P which will take a pair (Sj(q,i), j) as an input, and gives an answer of TRUE if S(q,i) eventually halts. By feeding the program itself we drive it into a never ending status which means halting problem cannot return an answer which means it will never return a solution, therefore problem is unsolvable. Contradiction that can be also justified with Cantor’s digitalization, that is also Godel’s incompleteness. P() = S(i, i)+ 1, if S(i, i)={0, 1}  P={1,0}. Question a program that is going to generate P, cannot generate P, therefore S is incomplete.

  37. S is a collection of the objects that are members of the set S. • fs(i) is a function which takes input iN, and returns “True 1 or False 0" (decision) for values that are/aren't members of the set, respectively.Define a function g which just asks, what does fs return if you give it ‘sS’ as an input? • 1) If fs(s) returns true, then g(s) returns True; if fs(s) returns False, then g(s) also returns False (declining f’s wrong decision, since sS). • 2) Think reverse scenario. sS, If fs(s) returns True, then g(s) must return False. • 1- g(s) is then a confirmation function for the set of all sets that do contain themselves as members. • 2- g(s) is also a confirmation function for the set of all sets that donot contain themselves as members. • Is g a member of itself? There are two different valid functions fitting to the definition of g - one which contains itself, and the other which doesn't contain itself: a flip of g: g'.

  38. Is g a member of itself? There are two different valid functions fitting to the definition of g - one which contains itself, one which doesn't. but just a flip of g: g'. • g‘(s) is the function for the set of all sets that do not contain themselves as members. if g'(s) returns true, s does not contain itself as member of S, that is s S. • Suppose s=g’, flipping regions. • Inconsistency of g'. (Russel’s paradox): if g'(g') returns true, then g' is a member of itself, which is wrong, so g'(g') should have been false. And if g'(g') returns false, then that means that g' is not a member of itself, which means that g'(g') should have returned true.

  39. We say that the elements of a set can be counted if they can be listed in a single sequence. N, neg or positive wouldn’t matter. • Cantor’s D. • Anything that can be computed according to a finite list of rules, can be computed by one of TM. Consistent • Briefly, a Turing machine can be thought of as a black box, which performs a calculation of some kind on an input number. If the calculation reaches a conclusion, or halts then an output number is returned. • One of the consequences of Turing's theory is that there is a Universal (GENERIC) Turing machine, in other words one which can simulate all possible Turing machines. This means that we can think of the Turing machines as countable and listed T1, T2,... by a Universal Machine through a sort of alphabetical listing. Turing used this to describe his own version of Gödel's Theorem: that there is no mechanical procedure for telling whether a Turing machine will halt on a given input: the Halting Problem.

  40. The set of functions is uncountable, the set of turing machines (programs) is countable, therefore there are more functions than programs. By the diagonal argument Turing proves that the existence of a TM that decides the halting problem is contradictory. • Let's represent the result of using the nth Turing machine, Tn on the input i as Tn(i). Suppose that there was a rule or procedure for deciding whether or not Tn(i) halts for all values of n and i. • But then by a similar diagonalising procedure, we can define a new Turing machine, say D, which will halt for all inputs and return the following output for input i: • 0 if Ti(i) does not halt. • Ti(i)+1 if Ti(i) does halt. • But this machine D must be one of those machines, in other words it must be Td for some d. However, we just defined it to give a different answer from Td with input d. Contradiction. • The extra sophistication here over the original diagonalising argument lies in all the listing done is itself computable and any machine Tn may or may not halt in carrying out its computations. None of this enters into Cantor's original diagonal argument.

  41. Computable sequences • A sequence f(i) is computable if there is a program (Machine) for given input i computes f(i). • Gödel proved his Completeness Theorem, namely that a formula is provable from the axioms iff it is valid. • Godel's First InCompleteness Theorem. Any adequate axiomatizable theory is incomplete.  In particular the sentence "This sentence is not provable" is true but not provable in the theory. Enumerate • Godel's Second Incompleteness Theorem. In any consistent axiomatizable theory (axiomatizable means the axioms can be computably generated) which can encode sequences of numbers (and thus the syntactic notions of "formula", "sentence", "proof") the consistency of the system is not provable in the system. • The Liar Paradox. "Truth" for English sentences is not definable in English. Proof. Suppose it is. Then so is its complement "False". Let   s   be the sentence "This sentence is false" . Since the phrase "This sentence" refers to   s,   we have s   iff   "This sentence is false"   iff   "s is false"   iff   not   s. A contradiction to the statement. “Everything I say is a lie, I am lying”

  42. What can be computable in principle • Alonzo Church defined the Lambda calculus, • Kurt Gödel defined Recursive functions, • Stephen Kleene defined Formal systems, • Markov defined, Markov algorithms, • Emil Post and Alan Turing defined abstract machines now known as Post machines and Turing machines. • Church Turing thesis. Anything computable with these computational methodologies is computable by a Turing machine. • Earlier 1900, David Hilbert believed that all of mathematics could be precisely axiomatized. Once this LIST was completed, there would be an “effective procedure”, i.e., an algorithm that would accept any precise mathematical statement as input, and, after a finite number of steps, it would reach to decisionwhether the statement was true or false. YES or NO statement. • Hilbert was introducing what is called now a decision procedure for all of mathematics.

  43. Satisfiable and Valid Structures • “Hilbert considered the validity problem for first-order logic”. First-order logic is a mathematical language in which most mathematical statements can be formulated. This is a special case of decision problem. • Every statement in first-order logic has a precise meaning in every appropriate logical structure, i.e., it is true or false in each such structure. Those statements that are true in every appropriate structure are called valid. Those statements that are true in some structure are called satisfiable. • Notice that a formula, Φ, is valid iff its negation, ¬Φ, is not satisfiable. • Hilbert calls First Order Logic as entscheidungsproblem. • In a textbook, Principles of Mathematical Logic by Hilbert and Ackermann, the authors wrote, “The Entscheidungsproblem is solved when we know a procedure that allows for any given logical expression to decide by finitely many operations its validity or satisfiability. SAT or 3SAT.. Etc..

  44. Axioms and Inference rules. • 1930, Gödel’s presents a complete axiomatization of first-order logic, based on the Principia Mathematica by Whitehead and Russell • He proves in his Completeness Theorem, that a formula is provable from the axioms iff it is valid. • In particular, since the axioms are easily recognizable, and rules of inference very simple, there is a mechanical procedure that can LIST out all proofs. • Each line in a proof is either an axiom, or a inference following from the previous lines by one of the simple rules. • For any given string of characters, we can tell if it is a proof. • Thus we can systematically list all strings of characters and check whether each one is a proof. If so, then we can add the proof's last line to our list of theorems. • In this way, we can list out all theorems, i.e., exactly all the valid formulas of first-order logic, can be listed out by a simple mechanical procedure.

  45. More precisely, the set of valid formulas is the range of a computable function. In modern terminology we say that the set of valid formulas of first-order logic is recursively enumerable (r.e.). • “Yes, Φ is valid.” However, if Φ were not valid then we might never find this fact out. The list of all the non-valid formulas, or the list of all satisfiable formulas. • Gödel’s Incompleteness Theorem: there is no complete and computable axiomatization of the first-order theory of the natural numbers. That is, there is no reasonable list of axioms from which we can prove exactly all true statements of number theory (Gödel 1931). • Church and Turing independently prove that the entscheidungsproblem is unsolvable. Turing’s unsolvability of halting problem.

  46. Application of halting: Goldbach’ s conjecture • Conjecture: (even n)  (n2), can be represented with two prime numbers p and q as n=p+q. • That could be disproven via counterexample by simulating an n-state TM, such that quits (halts-if the result is TRUE) if finds a counterexample, an even n  (p+q), {p, q}primes. Then the conjecture will be disproven. • If the result is FALSE, then the conjecture is proven. That means halting algorithm for this problem must not halt.

  47. FSM, Busy Beaver. Next week.

More Related