1 / 32

Artificial Intelligence 9. Resolution Theorem Proving

Artificial Intelligence 9. Resolution Theorem Proving. Course V231 Department of Computing Imperial College Jeremy Gow. The Full Resolution Rule. If Unify(P j , ¬ Q k ) =  ( ¬ makes them unifiable) P 1  …  P m , Q 1  …  Q n

virgilj
Download Presentation

Artificial Intelligence 9. Resolution Theorem Proving

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. Artificial Intelligence 9. Resolution Theorem Proving Course V231 Department of Computing Imperial College Jeremy Gow

  2. The Full Resolution Rule • If Unify(Pj, ¬Qk) =  (¬ makes them unifiable) P1 …  Pm, Q1  …  Qn Subst(, P1  … (no Pj) …  Pm  Q1  … (no Qk) ... Qn) • Pj and Qk are resolved • Arbitrary number of disjuncts • Relies on preprocessing into CNF

  3. A More Concise Version E.g. for A = {1, 2, 7} first clause is L1 L2  L7

  4. Resolution Proving • Knowledge base of clauses • Start with the axioms and negation of theorem in CNF • Resolve pairs of clauses • Using single rule of inference (full resolution) • Resolved sentence contains fewer literals • Proof ends with the empty clause • Signifies a contradiction • Must mean the negated theorem is false • (Because the axioms are consistent) • Therefore the original theorem was true

  5. Empty Clause means False • Resolution theorem proving ends • When the resolved clause has no literals (empty) • This can only be because: • Two unit clauses were resolved • One was the negation of the other (after substitution) • Example: q(X) and ¬q(X) or: p(X) and ¬p(bob) • Hence if we see the empty clause • This was because there was an inconsistency • Hence the proof by refutation

  6. Resolution as Search • Initial State: Knowledge base (KB) of axioms and negated theorem in CNF • Operators: Resolution rule picks 2 clauses and adds new clause • Goal Test: Does KB contain the empty clause? • Search space of KB states • We want proof (path) or just checking (artefact)

  7. Aristotle’s Example (Again) • Socrates is a man and all men are mortal Therefore Socrates is mortal • Initial state 1) is_man(socrates) 2) is_man(X)  is_mortal(X) 3) ¬is_mortal(socrates) (negation of theorem) • Resolving (1) & (2) gives new state (1)-(3) & 4) is_mortal(socrates)

  8. Aristotle’s Example: Search Space 1) is_man(socrates) 2) is_man(X)  is_mortal(X) 3) ¬is_mortal(socrates) 4) is_mortal(socrates) 1) is_man(socrates) 2) is_man(X)  is_mortal(X) 3) ¬is_mortal(socrates) 1) is_man(socrates) 2) ¬is_man(X)  is_mortal(X) 3) ¬is_mortal(socrates) 4) ¬is_man(socrates) 1) is_man(socrates) 2) is_man(X)  is_mortal(X) 3) ¬is_mortal(socrates) 4) is_mortal(socrates) 5) False 1) is_man(socrates) 2) is_man(X)  is_mortal(X) 3) ¬is_mortal(socrates) 4) ¬is_man(socrates) 5) False

  9. Resolution Proof Tree (Proof 1)

  10. Resolution Proof Tree (Proof 2)

  11. Reading Proof Tree 2 You said that all men were mortal. That means that for all things X, either X is not a man, or X is mortal [CNF step]. If we assume that Socrates is not mortal, then, given your previous statement, this means Socrates is not a man [first resolution step]. But you said that Socrates is a man, which means that our assumption was false [second resolution step], so Socrates must be mortal.

  12. Russell & Norvig Example

  13. Reminder: Kowalski NF • Can reintroduce  to CNF, e.g. ¬A  ¬C  B becomes (A  C)  B • Kowalski normal form (A1… An)  (B1 … Bn) • Resolve in KNF using ‘KNF style’ rules • e.g. Binary resolution… AB, BC AC

  14. R&N Example: Kowalski NF

  15. R&N Example: Proof Tree

  16. R&N Example: Prover9 Input

  17. R&N Example: Prover9 Proof

  18. Equality Axioms • is_pres(obama) and is_pres(b_obama) • will not unify (syntactically different) • unification algorithm does not allow this • Even if we add to the knowledge base: • obama = b_obama • Solution: add equality axioms to KB • X=X, X=YY=X, etc. • Special axiom for every predicate/function: • X = Y  P(X) = P(Y)

  19. Equality & Demodulation • Alternative solution: rewrite with equalities • Demodulation inference rule X=Y, A[S] Subst(, A[Y]) • Two input clauses (one an equality X=Y) • Unify X with a subterm S of other • Apply unifier to clause with subterm Y (not S) • Also works unifying with Y and putting in X Unify(X, S) = 

  20. Heuristic Strategies • Pure resolution search tends to be slow • For interesting problems • Many clauses in the initial knowledge base • Each step adds a new clause (which can be used) • Num. of possible resolution combinations explodes • Selection Heuristics • Intelligently choose which pair to resolve • Pruning Heuristics • Forbid certain pairs

  21. Unit Preference Strategy • Prefer to resolve unit clauses • Contain only a single literal • Selection heuristic • Searching for smallest (empty) clause • Resolving with the unit clauses keeps small • Very effective early on for simple problems • Doesn’t reduce branching rate for medium problems

  22. Set of Support Strategy • Distinguished subset of KB clauses • Set of support (SOS) clauses • Every step must involve SOS (pruning heuristic) • Must be careful not to lose completeness • Example SOS strategy: • Initial SOS is negated theorem • Add new clauses to SOS • Hence False will be deduced (strategy is complete) • Many provers use SOS, e.g. Prover9

  23. Input Resolution Strategy • Special case of SOS strategy • SOS = clauses in the initial knowledge base • Clearly reduces search space • Every resolution must involve an original clause • So number of possible resolutions grows slowly • Not complete for first order logic • But complete for Horn-clauses, e.g. Prolog

  24. Subsumption • Clause C subsumes clause D • if C is more ‘general’ (D is more specific) • Naive check for subsumption • Select C2, a subset of literals of C • Find Unify(C2, D) =  •  does not add anything to D (only renames vars) • Example: • p(george) ∨ q(X) subsumed by p(A) ∨ q(B) ∨ r(C) • Substitution: {A/george, X/B} • Second clause is more general

  25. Subsumption Strategy • Check each new clause is not subsumed by KB • Complete strategy • Specific clauses can be inferred from general ones • So we can throw specific clauses away • Reduced search space still contains False • Can be inefficient • expense must be outweighed by the reduction in the search space

  26. Applications: Axioms for Algebras • Bill McCune and Larry Wos • Argonne National Laboratories • FO resolution provers: EQP, Otter, Prover9 • Robbins Problem (axioms of Boolean algebras) • Stated 60+ years ago, mathematicians failed • 1996: EQP solved in 8 days in 1996 (+human work) • General application to algebraic axiomatisations • Generate possible axioms for algebras • Prove new axioms equivalent to old

  27. Applications: Theory Formation • Simon’s HR system: Automated Theory Formation • Used in mathematical (and bioinformatics) domains • Theories = concepts, examples, conjectures, proofs • HR uses Otter to prove conjectures it makes • Effective in algebraic domains • See notes for anti-associative algebra results • Otter not so effective in number theory • Used as a ‘triviality’ filter (discard theorems it can prove) • Example conjectures made by HR (and proved by Simon): • Sum of divisors is prime → number of divisors is prime • Sum of divisors of a square is an odd number • Perfect numbers are pernicious [and many more…..]

  28. Inductive Theorem Proving • Deduction by mathematical induction • Induction over many different structures • Allows reasoning about recursion/iteration • Useful for hardware/software verification • Don’t confuse inductive learning (next lecture)

  29. Interactive Theorem Proving • Necessary to interact with humans in order to prove theorems of any difficulty • Mathematician’s assistant • Let a theorem prover do simple tasks while you develop a theory (e.g., Buchberger’s Theorema) • Guided theorem prover • User follows and guides computer proof attempt • Needs visualisation tools for proof trees

  30. Higher Order Theorem Proving • Deduction in higher order logics • See lecture 4 • Allows more natural and succinct statements • Logics much less well-behaved • HOL theorem prover • Larry Paulson’s group in Cambridge • Has been used for verification tasks • E.g. verification of crytographic protocols • Uses induction and interactive control

  31. Proof Planning • Initially Alan Bundy’s group in Edinburgh • Human proofs often follow a similar structure • Express this as a outline plan • Methods represent a patterns of deduction • Outline plan guides proof search • Results in specific plan for theorem • Critics deal with common problems • Particularly useful for inductive theorems • Proof of base case and step case follow pattern

  32. Databases & Competitions • TPTP library (Sutcliffe & Suttner) • Thousands of Problems for Theorem Provers • Benchmarks for first order provers • HR is only non-human to add to this library • Annual CASC competition (Sutcliffe et al.) • Which is fastest/most accurate FO prover on planet? • Uses blind selection from the TPTP library • 2002-08 champion: Vampire (Voronkov & Riazonov)

More Related