1 / 29

Lecture 2 –

Lecture 2 –. Chapter 2. The Logic of Quantified Statements. Section 2.1. Predicates and Quantified Statements I. Predicates. A predicate is a sentence that contains a finite number of variables, and becomes a statement when values are substituted for the variables.

yagil
Download Presentation

Lecture 2 –

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. Lecture 2 –

  2. Chapter 2 The Logic of Quantified Statements

  3. Section 2.1 Predicates and Quantified Statements I

  4. Predicates • A predicate is a sentence that • contains a finite number of variables, and • becomes a statement when values are substituted for the variables. • “x flies like a y.” • Let x be “time” and y be “arrow.” • Let x be “fruit” and y be “banana.”

  5. Domains of Predicate Variables • The domainD of a predicate variable x is the set of all values that x may take on. • Let P(x) be the predicate. • x is a free variable. • The truth set of P(x) is the set of all values of xD for which P(x) is true.

  6. The Universal Quantifier • The symbol  is the universal quantifier. • The statement xS, P(x) means “for all x in S, P(x),” where SD. • x is a bound variable, bound by the quantifier . • The statement is true if P(x) is true for allx in S. • The statement is false if P(x) is false for at leastonex in S.

  7. Examples • Statement • “7 is a prime number” is true. • Predicate • “x is a prime number” is neither true nor false. • Statements • “x {2, 3, 5, 7}, x is a prime number” is true. • “x {2, 3, 6, 7}, x is a prime number” is false.

  8. Examples of Universal Statements • x {1, …, 10}, x2 > 0. • x {1, …, 10}, x2 > 100. • xR, x3 – x 0. • xR, yR, x2 + xy + y2 0. • x, x2 > 100.

  9. The Existential Quantifier • The symbol  is the existential quantifier. • The statement xS, P(x) means “there exists x in S such that P(x),” SD. • x is a bound variable, bound by the quantifier . • The statement is true if P(x) is true for at least onex in S. • The statement is false if P(x) is false for allx in S.

  10. Examples of Existential Statements • x {1, …, 10}, x2 > 0. • x {1, …, 10}, x2 > 100. • xR, x3 – x 0. • xR, yR, x2 + xy + y2 0. • x, x2 > 100.

  11. Negations of Universal Statements • The negation of xS, P(x) is the statement xS, P(x). • If “xR, x2 > 10” is false, then “xR, x2 10” is true.

  12. Negations of Existential Statements • The negation of xS, P(x) is the statement xS, P(x). • If “xR, x2 < 0” is false, then “xR, x2 0” is true.

  13. Example: Negation of a Universal Statement • p = “Everybody likes me.” • Express p as x {all people}, x likes me. • p is the statement x {all people}, x does not like me. • p = “Somebody does not like me.”

  14. Example: Negation of an Existential Statement • p = “Somebody likes me.” • Express p as x {all people}, x likes me. • p is the statement x {all people}, x does not like me. • p = “Everyone does not like me.” • p = “Nobody likes me.”

  15. Lecture 8 – Jan 29, 2002

  16. Section 2.2 Predicates and Quantified Statements II

  17. Multiply Quantified Statements • Multiply quantified universal statements • xS, yT, P(x, y) • The order does not matter. • Multiply quantified existential statements • xS, yT, P(x, y) • The order does not matter.

  18. Multiply Quantified Statements • Mixed universal and existential statements • xS, yT, P(x, y) • yT, xS, P(x, y) • The order does matter. • What is the difference? • Compare • xR, yR, x + y = 0. • yR, xR, x + y = 0.

  19. Negation of Multiply Quantified Statements • Negate the statement xR, yR, zR, x + y + z = 0. • (xR, yR, zR, x + y + z = 0) xR, (yR, zR, x + y + z = 0) xR, yR, (zR, x + y + z = 0) xR, yR, zR, (x + y + z = 0) xR, yR, zR, x + y + z 0

  20. Negate the statement “Every positive integer can be written as the sum of three squares.” • (nZ, a, b, cZ, n = a2 + b2 + c2). • nZ, (a, b, cZ, n = a2 + b2 + c2). • nZ, a, b, cZ, (n = a2 + b2 + c2). • nZ, a, b, cZ, na2 + b2 + c2. • Is the original statement true?

  21. Universal Conditional Statements • A universal conditional statement is of the form xS, P(x) Q(x). • The converse is xS, Q(x) P(x). • The inverse is xS, P(x) Q(x). • The contrapositive is xS, Q(x) P(x).

  22. Negation of Universal Conditional Statements • Negate the statement xR, x < 10 x2 < 100. • (xR, x < 10 x2 < 100) xR, (x < 10 x2 < 100) xR, (x < 10)  (x2 100). • Which one is true?

  23. Putnam Question A-2 (1981) • Two distinct squares of the 8 by 8 chessboard C are said to be adjacent if they have a vertex or side in common. • Also, g is called a C-gap if for every numbering of the squares of C with all the integers 1, 2, …, 64, there exist two adjacent squares whose numbers differ by at least g. • Determine the largest C-gap g.

  24. Putnam Question A-2 (1981) • Consider the standard numbering • Note that the largest difference is 9.

  25. Putnam Question A-2 (1981) • Could the answer be 9? • 9 is the largest C-gap if • 9 is a C-gap, and • 10 is not a C-gap.

  26. Putnam Question A-2 (1981) • 10 is not a C-gap if • There exists a numbering of the squares such that no two adjacent squares differ by at least 10. • Equivalently, there exists a numbering of the squares such that every two adjacent squares differ by at most 9. • We have just seen that this is true. • Therefore, 10 is not a C-gap.

  27. Putnam Question A-2 (1981) • Is 9 a C-gap? • Consider the two squares that are labeled #1 and #64. • There is a path of at most 8 squares linking square #1 and square #64.

  28. Putnam Question A-2 (1981) • One possible numbering and path

  29. Putnam Question A-2 (1981) • Of the 7 differences along this path, one must be at least 9, since the total difference is 63. • Therefore, 9 is a C-gap.

More Related