1 / 53

Part A-III (continued) Microeconomic Theory Review (continued)

Part A-III (continued) Microeconomic Theory Review (continued). Economics One-on-One. The limitations of the Market Model Game Theory A model of Bargaining. To begin with. Remember trading is ‘good’

Download Presentation

Part A-III (continued) Microeconomic Theory Review (continued)

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. Part A-III (continued)Microeconomic Theory Review (continued) Intro_E

  2. Economics One-on-One • The limitations of the Market Model • Game Theory • A model of Bargaining Intro_E

  3. To begin with Remember trading is ‘good’ Voluntary exchange of anything between any two agents improves the wellbeing of both agents (people, firms – parties) Voluntary exchange generally represents a Pareto Improvement Generally? Why generally? Remember the concept of market failures: -Monopoly (monopsony) -Externalities -Public goods -Severe informational asymmetries Intro_E

  4. Market failures aside, One primary goal of any economic system is to structure itself so as to facilitate voluntary exchange among the economic agents. By ‘facilitate’ we mean Make it ‘easy and cheap’ - minimize transaction costs More on this later Intro_E

  5. Recall, a market is any coming together of buyers and sellers Markets help facilitate voluntary exchange (trading) and trading generally increases wellbeing – they lower the cost of trading In first and second year you learn about the ‘market model’. This is one particular model of how trading occurs. The ‘market model’ describes the process of trading - coordinating the utility and profit maximizing behaviour of many independent of individual agents Intro_E

  6. The ‘market model’ is intended to explain how trading takes place when there are manyrelatively small individual agents coming together to trade in a relatively large and very impersonal environment. - a farmer selling wheat - you buying apples No individual buyer or seller can affect the outcome – each agent acts independently. Welfare improving trades occur at a price set by ‘the market’ Intro_E

  7. The market model Market for Apples Price of apples Supply of apples (all potential apple producers) Pe Demand for apples (all potential apple consumers) Qe Quantity of apples Intro_E

  8. Limitations of the market model • Many buyers and/or sellers • All buyers are buying and all sellers are selling the same (or similar) item • Perfect (very good) information • Price is known • Price is ‘given’ (accepted) by buyers and sellers (or at least one of the buying side or selling side) Intro_E

  9. But what if ? • There is only one buyer and one seller (or just a few decisions makers) • The item being sold is more or less unique • There is no established market price set prior to trading Can voluntary exchange (trading) still take place? - YES Will it be welfare improving? – GENERALLY What can the market model say about the process of trading? – NOT MUCH What can economic theory say about the process of trading and the outcome? - LOTS Intro_E

  10. Economics One-on-One - few decision makers (agents) - the optimal decision of each agent depends on the decision of the other agents - interdependence In such a situation, each agent must formulate a ‘strategy’ which accounts for the possible decisions of the other agents. This is a ‘game’ - poker, football, bridge, dating, politics, war, whatever. Intro_E

  11. Courts and lawyers (The Law) frequently deal with situations in which there are a few decision makers making decisions that are interdependent. Game theory is a formal method of analysis which allows us to understand (and predict) the behaviour of rational economic agents when there are a few agents making interdependent decisions. Intro_E

  12. Basic Game Theory The Basics of a game: - the players (economic agents) - the strategies of each player - the payoffs to each player under each strategy - determining each player’s optimal strategy and the game outcome Intro_E

  13. Example: Mary and John each want to sell something Situation: - two potential sellers of the same good (home owners, car owners, merchants contemplating a sale, etc.) - if Mary offers her good for sale and John does not, then Mary will earn $1. - if Mary offers her good for sale and John offers his good for sale, Mary will suffer a $2 loss. Intro_E

  14. - if John offers his good for sale and Mary does not, then John will earn $1. - if John offers his good for sale and Mary offers her good for sale, John will suffer a $2 loss. - if either seller does not sell, then that seller will break even. Intro_E

  15. In the above ‘Game’ Players: Mary and John Strategies: Sell or don’t sell Payoffs to each player under each strategy: (listed in the last two slides) The decisions of Mary and John are clearly interdependent. Each must consider what the other agent is going to do before they make their own decision Can we predict the outcome? What will Mary and John do? Intro_E

  16. Let’s consider what we know in the form of a ‘payoff matrix’: the value to each player for each of the possible outcomes PAYOFF MATRIX Mary’s decision SELL DON’T SELL John’s decision SELL (-$2, -$2) ( $1, $0) DON’T SELL ( $0, $1) ( $0, $0) (first entry in the round brackets represents John's payoff second entry represents Mary's payoff) Intro_E

  17. What will each player do? Consider Mary’s options and the resulting outcomes – the ‘extensive form’ or a ‘decision tree’ Mary’s payoff If John sells and Mary sells -$2 and Mary does not sell $0 If John does not sell and Mary sells $1 and Mary does not sell $0 Intro_E

  18. Assume that Mary and John do not cooperate – neither will tell the other agent what they intend to do Mary has no information on what John will do so she must assume that there is a 50/50 chance of him selling or not selling. In this case: the expected value to Mary if she sells is .5(-$2) + .5($1) = -$0.50 the expected value to Mary if she does not sell is .5($0) + .5($0) = $0 Intro_E

  19. Prediction: Mary will not sell What about John? How does he view the situation? In this particular non-cooperative game with no information – exactly the same way Intro_E

  20. John’s payoff If Mary sells and John sells -$2 and John does not sell $0 If Mary does not sell and John sells $1 and John does not sell $0 Intro_E

  21. If John has no information on what Mary will do so he also must assume that there is a 50/50 chance of her selling or not selling. In this case: the expected value to John if he sells is .5(-$2) + .5($1) = -$0.50 the expected value to John if he does not sell is .5($0) + .5($0) = $0 Intro_E

  22. Prediction: Both Mary and John will decide not to sell Is this a good outcome? It is the best that Mary and John can do in the situation: no information/no co-operation We would say that each player has a dominant strategy ‘ the optimal move for a player to make irrespective of the other player’s decision’ Intro_E

  23. In a sense, this is a pretty amazing result. Neither agent knows anything about the other agent’s expected payoffs (the nature of their utility or profit function) nor the other agent’s likely strategy. Each agent only knows their own utility or profit function. Yet in this particular non-cooperative game with no information we can predict how each agent will behave and the game outcome Intro_E

  24. Dominant strategies and equilibrium Since each player has a dominant strategy we can predict what each player will do (in this game – it is ‘not sell’) This leads to a prediction that the equilibrium for this game is such that neither Mary not John will offer their item for sale In this particular case the equilibrium is a Nash Equilibrium ‘no individual player can do any better by changing their decision so long as the other player does not change their decision’ For a non-repeated game this is it? Intro_E

  25. But is there a better outcome for Mary and John and for society? Is the solution in the above game a Pareto Optimum? Can Society as a whole do better? The game which we just described is a non-co-operative game with no information But what if Mary and John decide to meet and co-operate? Intro_E

  26. With no co-operation Mary and John ended up at the ($0, $0) payoff PAYOFF MATRIX Mary’s decision SELL DON’T SELL John’s decision SELL (-$2, -$2) ( $1, $0) DON’T SELL ( $0, $1) ( $0, $0) Are there better outcomes for John and Mary (and society) Intro_E

  27. What if John and Mary decide to co-operate (jointly maximize profits) PAYOFF MATRIX Mary’s decision SELL DON’T SELL John’s decision SELL (-$2, -$2) ( $1, $0) DON’T SELL ( $0, $1) ( $0, $0) Mary and John meet and decide that one of them will sell and one will not sell. Together they will make $1 in profit and then they will split the profit (say $0.50 each). Intro_E

  28. Solution to the game if there is co-operation Mary and John are each better off and society is better off – the co-operative outcome is a Pareto Improvement (at least one person is made better off and no one is made worse off). Actually three people can be made better off (Mary, John and the buyer). Trading is good and in this case co-operation among the players leads to trading which otherwise would not take place. Intro_E

  29. Variations on the ‘Mary and John want to sell something game’ Go back to no co-operation state but what if one player has information on the other player’s likely strategy? How could this happen? - reputation (watched this player play before) • espionage (industrial spying) • John (mistakenly) ‘sent’ a signal Intro_E

  30. Suppose Mary has reason to believe that there is a 75% chance that John will not sell Then Mary believes that the probability of John selling or not selling is 25/75. In this case: the expected value to Mary if she sells is .25(-$2) + .75($1) = $0.25 the expected value to Mary if she does not sell is .25($0) + .75($0) = $0 Intro_E

  31. What about John? If John has not acquired any new information then his best belief on what Mary will do remains that there is a 50/50 chance of her selling or not selling. In this case nothing has changed for John: the expected value to John if he sells is .5(-$2) + .5($1) = -$0.50 the expected value to John if he does not sell is .5($0) + .5($0) = $0 Intro_E

  32. Prediction: Mary will sell and earn $1 profit, John will not sell Mary’s dominant strategy has changed to sell while John’s remains don’t sell. So the model predicts that Mary will sell and John will not sell. PAYOFF MATRIX Mary’s decision SELL DON’T SELL John’s decision SELL (-$2, -$2) ( $1, $0) DON’T SELL ( $0, $1) ( $0, $0) Intro_E

  33. Is this still a Nash Equilibrium? Yes. Neither John nor Mary can improve their situation if the other player’s decision remains unchanged. Is it a Pareto Improvement? Yes. Trading takes place: poor John/fortunate Mary but economics does not care who wins, as long as no one loses. Two people have been made better off (Mary and the buyer) John is no worse off. Intro_E

  34. Variations on the ‘Mary and John want to sell something game’ What if the players value the outcomes differently? How could this happen? - Different taste (selling is more important to one than the other) • Different profit functions (one agent stands to gain more if they sell) • Different risk functions (one agent can deal with a loss if it occurs better than the other agent) Intro_E

  35. Suppose that John stands to gain $3 if he sells and Mary only $1. Then the payoff matrix is the following: PAYOFF MATRIX Mary’s decision SELL DON’T SELL John’s decision SELL (-$2, -$2) ( $3, $0) DON’T SELL ( $0, $1) ( $0, $0) Intro_E

  36. John’s payoff If Mary sells and John sells -$2 and John does not sell $0 If Mary does not sell and John sells $3 and John does not sell $0 Intro_E

  37. If John has no information on what Mary will do so he also must assume that there is a 50/50 chance of her selling or not selling. In this case: the expected value to John if he sells is .5(-$2) + .5($3) = $0.50 the expected value to John if he does not sell is .5($0) + .5($0) = $0 Intro_E

  38. John will sell but Mary will not sell. Again a Pareto Improvement outcome but John and the buyer are the ‘winners’ PAYOFF MATRIX Mary’s decision SELL DON’T SELL John’s decision SELL (-$2, -$2) ( $3, $0) DON’T SELL ( $0, $1) ( $0, $0) Intro_E

  39. Another Game: The Prisoner’s Dilemma(why they always get confessions on NYPD BLUE and Law & Order - or how the Boulder Police Department might have screwed-up.) Two individuals (Jack and Jill) are suspected of involvement in a crime Intro_E

  40. Situation: - two parents (Jack and Jill) are suspected of involvement in a crime, say child murder - Police only have circumstantial evidence and this it not enough to get a conviction. - if one (or both) of the suspects confess, then the prosecutor will get a conviction (possibly two convictions) The police/prosecutors need a confession. - no matter what, the child was harmed and the parents can be convicted of child neglect (a lesser crime Intro_E

  41. Here’s what the police do: First, each suspect is taken to a different room – no co-operation Jack is told • if you confess and implicate your partner and your partner does not confess, then • she will be charged with murder (25 years in prison) • you will be charged with a lesser crime (no time in prison). • if you confess and implicate your partner and your partner also confesses and implicates you, then • you will both be charged with manslaughter and each of you will spend 10 years in prison. Intro_E

  42. If neither of you parents confess, the prosecutor threatens to harass them publicly and ultimately charge them with child neglect for which they will spend up to 1 year in jail. Jill is told exactly the same thing Intro_E

  43. In the above ‘Game’ Players: Jack and Jill Strategies: Confess or don’t confess Payoffs’ to each player under each strategy: (listed in the last two slides) The decisions of Jack and Jill are clearly interdependent. Each must consider what the other agent is going to do before they make their own decision What will Jack and Jill do? What are their options? Intro_E

  44. What does the payoff matrix look like ? PAYOFF MATRIX Jill’s decision Confess Don’t confess Jack’s decision Confess (10 yrs, 10 yrs) (0 yrs, 25 yrs) Don’t confess (25 yrs, 0 yrs) (1 yr, 1 yr) (first entry in the round brackets represents Jack's payoff second entry represents Jill's payoff) Intro_E

  45. What will each player do? Consider Jill’s options and the resulting outcomes – the ‘extensive form’ or a ‘decision tree’ Jill’s payoff If Jack confesses and Jill confesses 10 yrs and Jill does not confess 25 yrs If Jack does not confess and Jill confesses 0 yrs and Jill does not confess 1 yr Intro_E

  46. Jack and Jill can not communicate so they cannot cooperate – neither can tell the other person what they intend to do If Jack confesses then Jill’s best response is to confess If Jack does not confess then Jill’s best option is to confess The game has been carefully constructed by the police/prosecutor so that a rational individual will choose to confess. In this game we need not consider the probabilities. Intro_E

  47. Prediction: Jill will confess and since Jack faces the exact same options his dominant strategy is also to confess They each end up spending 10 years in jail Jill’s decision Confess Don’t confess Jack’s decision Confess (10 yrs, 10 yrs) (0 yrs, 25 yrs) Don’t confess (25 yrs, 0 yrs) (1 yr, 1 yr) Intro_E

  48. What if Jack and Jill are allowed to co-operate, then what are they likely to do? They are likely to agree that neither will confess and each will spend 1 year in prison. Does guilt or innocence matter in determining the outcome? Yes and no. It must be the case that each feels that the threat of conviction on a lesser offence is real. Loyalty and the general nature of the relationship between the two suspects gets mixed in. Intro_E

  49. Recall the Ramsey Case in Colorado – Jon Benet Ramsey what if Mr. Ramsey committed the murder, Mrs. Ramsey knows he did since she arrived at the scene just after the crime was committed? Her natural tendency would be not to confess, since she did not commit the crime. However, what if Mr. Ramsey is a real creep and she believes that he might confess, implicating her and getting himself off free, while she spends 25 years in prison. Maybe she should confess, 10 years in prison is better than 25 years in prison. Intro_E

  50. What if Mr. and Mrs. Ramsey are both guilty but they care deeply for each other. Then neither would confess and both would spend 1 year in prison. But this is really just co-operation between the suspects, whether or not they are interviewed separately. The police always try to create mistrust among the suspects. In the good old days the Mafia got cooperation without any direct communication. If you squealed you died. The Mafia can be thought of a way of ensuring cooperative outcomes among a group of criminals. Intro_E

More Related