1 / 22

The Socratic Way

The Socratic Way. Beginnings. Philosophy What is it? It’s hard to say I’ll approach this obliquely Began in the West with the Greeks (about 500 BC) The ‘love of wisdom’ We begin real philosophy with Socrates (496-399BC). Socratic Method. Socrates wrote nothing

eleanorroy
Download Presentation

The Socratic Way

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. The Socratic Way

  2. Beginnings • Philosophy • What is it? • It’s hard to say • I’ll approach this obliquely • Began in the West with the Greeks (about 500 BC) • The ‘love of wisdom’ • We begin real philosophy with Socrates (496-399BC)

  3. Socratic Method • Socrates wrote nothing • Spent his life talking in the Athenian town square • Plato wrote down his dialogues • The early ones have Socrates’s ideas • The later ones have Plato’s thoughts • He claimed to know nothing • He thought seeking truth had to be a collaborative effort

  4. Socratic Method • Begin by claiming ignorance of some issue • Seek enlightenment from a person who knows • Show that they don’t know • End by having a better idea of what is to be known

  5. Socratic Method • Elenchus • Socrates asks all the questions. • The interlocutor must answer every question. • A definition or principle is sought from the interlocutor. • Socrates seeks clarification, gaining assent for various propositions. • These propositions are used to show that the proposed definition or principle is unsatisfactory.

  6. Euthyphro • Socrates meets Euthyphro on the way to the law courts • Euthyphro is going to prosecute his father for unlawfully causing death – a capital crime • His father had mistreated a slave to the point that he died • Euthyphro thinks it is the right and pious thing to do to prosecute in such cases • Socrates is going to be tried for impiety • He thinks this is a good time to have a philosophical discussion on piety

  7. Euthyphro Soc. Do you know enough about piety to be sure that bringing an action against your father is not itself impious? Euth. Yes, I have an exact knowledge of all such matters. Soc.Is piety in every action always the same? and impiety just whatever is impious?. Euth. Yes

  8. Euthyphro Euth. Piety is doing what I’m doing and prosecuting my father. After all, Zeus punished his father Cronus (who’d also punished his father Uranus) Soc. But aren’t there also other pious actions? Euth. Yes Soc. I don’t want a list of some pious actions: I want to know what principle makes them pious.

  9. Euthyphro Euth. The principle is this: piety is what the gods love and impiety is what they hate. Soc. OK. So let’s think about that. Do the gods quarrel amongst themselves? Euth. Yes Soc. And what sort of differences give rise to the sort of long-lasting quarrels that the gods have?

  10. Euthyphro Soc. I say that that sort of dispute arises when we differ over what is just or good or honourable: any other questions we can eventually resolve Euth. Sure Soc. And the gods’ quarrels must also be like this Euth. That seems to be true

  11. Euthyphro Soc. And doesn’t everyone love what they deem just and noble and hate the unjust and ignoble? Euth. Yes Soc. Then some things will be both loved by the gods and hated by the gods? Euth. Yes Soc.Aha! So you agree that some things are both pious and impious!

  12. Euthyphro • But: a contradiction can never be true • Nothing can be a thing loved by the gods and at the same time a thing not loved by the gods. • And: any proposition that yields a contradiction must be false • Therefore: piety can’t be ‘what is loved by the gods’

  13. Aporia • This argument doesn’t tell us what piety is; only what it is not • This is typical of Socrates’s arguments • We are left in a state of indecision and perplexity – which the Greeks called aporia • The Socratic style is called aporetic

  14. Philosophical Reflexivism • What’s the process in that argument • Find Euthyphro, who claims to knowwhat piety is • Get a definitionof piety • Derive consequencesfrom this definition • Identify a falsehood(contradiction) in the consequences • Concludethat the definition must be false • Conclude finally Euthyphro didn’t know what piety was

  15. Philosophical Reflexivism • That argument depended on an assumption that if you know what piety is then you can give a definition of it. • That assumption was typical for Socrates: If you say you know what X is, then you can define X • But is it a good assumption? • How might Euthyphro have continued the argument?

  16. Euthyphro’s reply Euth. You say I don’t know what piety is, so you clearly have an idea of what it is to know something. Do tell. Soc. Surely: to know something is to be able to define it Euth. And this applies to everything? Soc. Of course!

  17. Euthyphro’s reply Euth. Well, we’ll see about that. I ask you to look now at that man with the shiny head who is buying figs. Soc. That’s Cephalus. Ha ha. He’s bald. Euth. Bald? But I’m sure I can see a couple of hairs there. Soc. Not enough though. He’s definitely bald.

  18. Euthyphro’s reply Euth. If I added one more hair to his head would he still be bald? Soc. Yes. Euth. So a single hair doesn’t make the difference between baldness and non-baldness. OK, so what if I then added one more hair Soc. I think I get your point. Euth. Which is?

  19. Euthyphro’s reply Soc. Since I can’t tell you how many hairs make a bald man non-bald, I can’t define baldness, so I don’t know what baldness is. Euth. Almost! But I think we do know what baldness is. My real point is that there are lots of words like ‘bald’ that we use but can’t define. Soc. Ah, and so you reject my assumption that to know what baldness is to know its definition.

  20. Philosophical Reflexivism • That argument is an application of Socrates’s method to Socrates’s method. • A sort of meta-elenchus! • This sort of self analysis – reflexivity – is typical of philosophy The philosophizing mind never simply thinks about an object, it always, while thinking about any object, thinks also about its thought about that object. Philosophy may thus be called thought of the second degree, thought about thought.

  21. Philosophical Reflexivism • Could we take reflexivity as being definitive of philosophy? • No. Consider mathematics, history, sociology • If we can’t define philosophy, does that mean we can’t know what it is? • What do you think?

More Related