1 / 18

Chapter 14: Fair Division

Chapter 14: Fair Division. Part 5 – Defining Fairness. What is fair ?. Before we decide what is the definition of fair , lets define some other more specific terms…

elia
Download Presentation

Chapter 14: Fair Division

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. Chapter 14: Fair Division Part 5 – Defining Fairness

  2. What is fair ? • Before we decide what is the definition of fair, lets define some other more specific terms… • Proportional: We will say a fair-division method is proportional if and only if each of n participants gets what he or she considers to be at least 1/n of the total value of the object or objects divided. • Envy: We will say a participant to a fair-division method experiences envy if and only if he or she would prefer to trade his or her portion of the division with some other participant. • Envy-Free: We will say a fair-division method is envy-free if and only if no participant experiences envy.

  3. What is Fair ? • Pareto-Optimal: We will say a fair-division method is Pareto-optimal if and only if there are no possible exchanges or different allocations that would benefit at least one participant that doesn’t also make at least one other participant worse off. • Equitable: We will say a fair-division method is equitable if and only if each participant believes he or she has received the same fraction of the total value of the object or objects divided. • We will use each of these preceding terms to measure the fairness of methods of division. For example, later we will justify statements such as “the lone-divider method is fair in the sense that it is proportional, however it is not envy-free.” • We can speak of each of these terms defining different criteriaoffairness for the division of items (just like we did for fairness in voting).

  4. What is Fair ? • We will say a method of fair-division is fair if it satisfies one of the preceding criteria of fairness (either proportionality, envy-freeness, Pareto-optimality, or equitability) • Note that each of the criteria of fairness is satisfied if and only if every participant considers the allocation fair in that sense. • That is, as we have now defined it, a method of fair-division is fair (in some sense) if and only if every participant considers it to be fair (in that sense).

  5. What is Fair ? • Of course, we could work with other definitions of fairness. • Suppose several new employees begin working in an office and are given different parts of a large project to complete. Perhaps some of those employees could complain that the workload is unfair, for example perhaps they think their supervisor has less work, but regardless, we could say the assignment is “fair in the sense that the supervisor said it was fair” and leave it at that. Here, not all participants have equal claim to the workload – and maybe that really is fair.

  6. What is Fair ? • It is important to keep in mind assumptions implicit in our definitions. • As the preceding example illustrates, our definition of fairness is restricted to situations in which all participants to a division do have equal claim (or equal responsibility to share) in whatever is being divided. • Also, as illustrated by the example of the new employees with different workloads, perhaps some allocation can be considered fair but it does not satisfy any of the criteria we have defined. For this reason we often speak, for example, of fair-division methods being “fair in the sense of being proportional” or “fair in the sense of being equitable.”

  7. Theorem 1 Theorem 1: The adjusted winner procedure is fair in the sense that it is equitable, envy-free and Pareto-optimal. We do not consider a proof, however here are a few observations… • The adjusted winner procedure is equitable because the algorithm followed does not terminate until both parties receive an equal number of their original points. • The design of the adjusted winner procedure is to allocate items in a way that neither party would trade their allocation for what the other has received. • The order of transfer of items according to increasing point ratios is designed to guarantee the adjusted winner procedure is Pareto-optimal.

  8. Theorem 2 Theorem 2: Divide and Choose is proportional and envy-free. Proof: • By definition, divide and choose is a fair-division method for only two players. • Divide and choose is proportional because the divider can divide the object (or objects) so that he or she considers each part of the division to represent 1/2 of the original value. Also, the chooser may select either of the parts cut by the divider so that he or she receives a portion that represents at least 1/2 of the value as perceived by the chooser. • In divide and choose, once a player believes he has received at least 1/2 of the original value, that player would consider that the other player will not have received more than 1/2 of the value and would therefore not envy the other player.

  9. Theorem 3 Theorem 3: Divide and Choose is not Pareto-optimal. Proof: • Suppose two players consider dividing a cake that is half chocolate and half vanilla. Suppose one player, the divider, likes both vanilla and chocolate equally while the other player, the chooser, loves chocolate but hates vanilla. • Suppose the divider cuts the cake so that each piece is half chocolate and half-vanilla. In the eyes of the divider, this represents a proportional division – each will get half.

  10. Theorem 3 Theorem 3: Divide and Choose is not Pareto-optimal. Proof: (continued) • Notice that there is another allocation that will make the chooser happier without hurting the divider. In other words, this division is not Pareto-optimal. • By definition, a division procedure is Pareto-optimal if it always results in a division such that no other division could make one party better off without hurting at least one player. • In this case, if the divider cut the cake so that half was vanilla and half was chocolate, the divider would be equally happy (he liked both) and the chooser would be much happier – she only wanted chocolate.

  11. Theorem 4 Theorem 4: The lone divider method is proportional but not envy-free. • We could develop a formal proof of this statement by considering the previous discussion on the steps involved in the lone divided method. • Here is a brief discussion of how that would be done: • Remember that there are three possibilities that could result after division by the lone divider. It is clear that the first two possibilities result in allocations that are proportional. • That the third possibility also yields a proportional allocation is justified as follows: Suppose A, B and C are dividing a cake and A has divided the cake into parts x, y and z that he considers are worth 1/3 of the value of the cake. Suppose B and C only approve of part x. Then we give A part z and combine parts x and y into xy and let B and C use divide and choose to split xy. Now B and C each will consider this a proportional allocation because B and C did not approve of z and thus consider xy to be more than 2/3rds of the value of the cake. Because divide and choose is proportional, B and C will each get 1/2 of what is at least 2/3rds in their estimation and therefore at least 1/3rd of their estimation of the cake.

  12. Theorem 4 Theorem 4: The lone divider method is proportional but not envy-free. • Finally, it is clear that in every possibility that the divider (A) always gets a share he considers proportional. • Thus in each case all 3 players will always receive an allocation that he or she considers proportional. • To show that this method is not envy-free we consider the case where both choosers (B and C) both split the combined piece xy. • Suppose they split that piece in a way that A considers not equal. In that case, it is possible that while A receives what he considers to be at least 1/3 of the cake, he may consider what one of the other players received to be better than his share. Thus player A may envy one of the choosers.

  13. Theorem 5 Theorem 5: The last diminisher method is proportional but not envy-free. An outline of a proof would be as follows – • The last diminisher method begins with some player (say A) first cutting a piece of the object to be divided. Suppose all n players consider that piece to be not more than 1/n of the value of the object. Thus A takes that piece and exits. • Now suppose that as the process continues, player B cuts a piece that A considers to be more than 1/n of the original value. If all the remaining players consider that piece to be not more than 1/n of the original value, then B takes that piece and exits . However, A will envy the piece received by B • Thus, in spite of the fact that the to complete the last diminisher method all divisions must be considered no more than 1/n of the total value, it is possible that at least one player will envy another (like A will envy B in the discussion above).

  14. Theorem 6 Theorem 6: If a fair-division method is envy-free then it is proportional. (Note theorems 4 and 5 demonstrate that the converse is not true.) Proof: • We prove this statement by considering its equivalent contrapositive: “If a fair-division method is not proportional then it is not envy-free.” • We can prove this to be true as follows: • Suppose a fair division method is not proportional. Then one of n players (say P1) believes that he or she did not receive at least 1/n of the total value in the division. Thus, that player believes the total value shared by the other players is more than (n-1)/n of the value. Then, if that is true, one of the other n-1 players must have more than 1/n of the total value. Thus P1 will envy that player. • To understand the previous argument, you might try in the case n = 3 or n = 4.

  15. Theorem 7 Theorem 7: The Selfridge-Conway method of fair division is proportional and envy-free. Proof: • First, because of theorem 6, we need only show that Selfridge-Conway is envy-free. By theorem 6, if it is envy-free then it is also proportional. • To show it is envy-free we must reconsider the Selfridge-Conway division process: • Remember there were two stages in this division method and we considered this method only in the case of three players. We will show no player experiences envy in the first stage and then no player experiences envy in the second stage…

  16. Theorem 7 Theorem 7: The Selfridge-Conway method of fair division is proportional and envy-free. Proof: (continued) • In the first stage of the Selfridge-Conway division procedure, player 1 will cut the object into three pieces. He would be equally happy with any of these pieces. Now player 2 might trim one of the three pieces to make at least a two-way tie for best piece among the three. If player 2 does trim a piece he will have to take that piece if player 3 doesn’t take it. Now player 3 will experience no envy in stage 1 because he is the first to choose. Player 2 will experience no envy because he can pick one of the two that were tied for best and player 1 will experience no envy because there will always remain an untrimmed piece after the others have taken theirs.

  17. Theorem 7 Theorem 7: The Selfridge-Conway method of fair division is proportional and envy-free. Proof: (continued) • If there are no trimmings left from stage 1 then the division is done and stage 2 is not needed – no players experienced envy. • If there are trimmings left from stage 1 then we can show the steps involved in stage 2 insure no player will experience envy. • Remember, initially, either player 2 or 3 did not receive a trimmed piece and that player will cut the trimmings and choose last from the trimmings. • Now the player that got the trimmed piece will pick first from the trimmings and envies no one because he picks first. • Player 1 picks second from the trimmings and will not envy the player that went before him because that player got a trimmed piece in stage 1 and only gets a portion of the trimmings from that piece. Player 1 also does not envy the other player because he is picking before him. • The last player to choose from the trimmings in stage 2 envies no one because he had cut the trimmings into what he considered equal pieces.

  18. Fair Division Theorems - Summary Theorem 1: The adjusted winner procedure is fair in the sense that it is equitable, envy-free and Pareto-optimal. Theorem 2: Divide and Choose is proportional and envy-free. Theorem 3: Divide and Choose is not Pareto-optimal. Theorem 4: The Lone Divider method is proportional but not envy-free. Theorem 5: The Last Diminisher method is proportional but not envy-free. Theorem 6: If a fair-division method is envy-free then it is proportional. Theorem 7: The Selfridge-Conway method is proportional and envy-free.

More Related