330 likes | 542 Views
Econ 805 Advanced Micro Theory 1. Dan Quint Fall 2008 Lecture 2 – Sept 4 2008. Today. Common auction formats The Independent Private Values model. Common Auction Formats and Strategic Equivalences. Dutch Auction.
E N D
Econ 805Advanced Micro Theory 1 Dan Quint Fall 2008 Lecture 2 – Sept 4 2008
Today • Common auction formats • The Independent Private Values model
Dutch Auction • Auctioneer begins at a high price and lowers it until a buyer claims the object at the current price • A slightly abstracted view: the price falls continuously (on a clock) instead of in increments • In a literal sense, a bidder’s strategy can be thought of as a choice of whether or not to buy at each price; but for practical purposes, it can be reduced to a decision of at what price to shout “mine!” if the item’s still available
“Sealed Tender” or “First-Price” Auction • Each bidder submits a sealed bid • The object goes to the bidder with the highest bid, at that price • A strategy is simply a choice of how much to bid
Dutch Auction = First-Price Auction • If all the matters is who wins the object and how much they pay, then the Dutch Auction and the First-Price Auction are equivalent • In each, a bidder’s strategy is reduced to picking a number; the highest number wins, and pays that much
English (Ascending) Auction • Think of art auctions • Price begins low; auctioneer solicits bids at the next price, keeps naming higher prices until no one is willing to raise their bid • Or, bidders name their own prices until no one is willing to outbid the high bidder – think of online auctions without proxy bidding • High bidder pays what he bid
Simplified English Auction (or Button Auction) • Price begins low, rises continuously • At each price, bidders can remain active (hold down a button) or drop out permanently • Bidders only know the current price (not who has dropped out and at what price) • When the second-to-last bidder drops out, the last man standing pays the current price • A bidder’s strategy can be reduced to choosing a price at which to drop out if he hasn’t won
Second-Price (or Vickrey) Auction • Each bidder submits a sealed bid • The object goes to the highest bidder, but the price they pay is the second-highest bid
Simplified English = Second-Price • Again, if we reduce the game to the question of who wins and how much they pay, the Simplified English Auction and Second Price Auction are equivalent • Strategies are reduced to picking a number • Highest number wins; payment is second-highest number • But the Simplified English Auction changes if bidders can see who is still active at each price • If I’m unsure of the exact value of the object, I may revise my estimate depending on how other bidders bid • Then strategies can no longer be reduced to picking a single number, and the equivalence breaks down
All-Pay Auctions and Wars of Attrition • In an All-Pay Auction, bidders submit sealed bids, the high bid wins the object, but everyone pays what they bid • All-Pay Auctions are sometimes used to model lobbying, attempts to buy political influence, and patent races – the losers already made their contributions or incurred their costs • War of Attrition is the same, but dynamic – like an all-pay button auction where bidders can see who’s still active • Great game for an undergrad game theory class – auction off a $20 bill, highest bid wins, highest two bids both pay what they bid
Multi-Unit Auctions with Unit Demand • Suppose there are k > 1 identical items for sale, but each bidder can only have one • “Pay-as-bid” auction is like a first-price auction – the k highest bidders win and pay their bids • Analog to the second-price auction is the “k+1st-price” auction • Button auction works similarly, ends when the k+1st bidder left drops out
Baseline model of an auction as a Bayesian Game: Symmetric Independent Private Values • N > 1 bidders in an auction for a single object • Nature moves first, assigning each bidder a private valuation vi for the object • Each bidder’s value vi is an independent draw from a common probability distribution F • Each bidder knows his own value vi but not that of his opponents • Bidder i’s payoff is vi – p if he wins, 0 if he loses, where p is the price he pays for the object • Like the Cournot game, i’s payoff depends on j’s type only through j’s action – this is what’s meant by “private values”
Note all the implicit assumptions we’re making • The number of bidders is fixed – there is no decision over whether or not to participate • Each bidder knows his own valuation perfectly, does not care what the other bidders think of the object • The bidders are symmetric ex-ante – valuations are drawn from the same distribution, which is common knowledge • Valuations are statistically independent • Bidders are risk-neutral
Auctions to sell versus auctions to buy • Suppose the government holds an auction for a contract to provide some service • Bids are now offers to provide the service at a given price, and the lowest bid wins • Where buyers were distinguished by their valuations for winning their object, firms can be thought of as distinguished by their cost of providing the service • So firm i’s payoffs would be p – ci, where p is the price received, and all the same analysis goes through
Solving for Equilibrium in the First- and Second-Price Auctions
Second-price (Vickrey) auctions in the IPV world • Claim. In a second-price sealed-bid auction, submitting a bid equal to your value is a weakly dominant strategy • Proof. Let B be the highest of your opponents’ bids. • When B > v, you could only win the object at price B, for a payoff of v – B < 0; bidding b = v gives you 0, which is as good as you can do • When B < v, any bid b > B gives the same payoff, v – B > 0, which is payoff from bidding b = v and the best you can do • When B = v, any bid gives the same payoff, 0 • Corollary. Every bidder playing the strategy bi(vi) = vi is a Bayesian Nash Equilibrium of the second-price auction
Similarly… • In a button auction, it’s a dominant strategy to drop out when the price reaches your private value vi • Doesn’t matter if you can observe who’s already dropped out or not • In an open-outcry ascending auction… • Equilibrium strategies are not clear • But it is a dominant strategy to never bid above your private value vi, nor to let the auction end at price below vi – d (where d is the minimum bid increment) • So any equilibrium will involve the highest-value bidder winning (unless the highest two are within d of each other), and paying within d of the second-highest value • So with private values, as d gets small, second-price or button auctions give approximately the same outcome as ascending auctions • Also similar is a first-price auction with proxy bidding, a la eBay • Bidders can name a maximum, then the computer raises their bid to the minimum required to win until that maximum is reached
Sadly, “everyone bids their value” is not the only equilibrium of the second-price auction • Suppose bidder values were drawn from a distribution with support [0,10] • The following is an equilibrium of the second-price auction: • Bidder 1 bids 15 regardless of his type • All other bidders bid 0 regardless of their type • bi(vi)=vi is “nearly” the only symmetric equilibrium; and it involves bidders playing a strict best-response at nearly every type; and it’s the equilibrium we’ll focus on
First-price auctions in the symmetric IPV world • We’ll look for “nice” equilibria: • Symmetric (bidders all play the same strategy) • Bids are increasing in valuations • Tomorrow, we’ll learn a trick that makes finding this type of equilibrium much easier • Suppose such an equilibrium exists, and letb : [0,V] R+ be the common bid function; then at a given type v, b(v) must be a solution to max x ÎR+(v – x) Pr(win | bid x, opponents bid b(-)) = max x ÎR+(v – x) Pr(b(vj) < x " j ¹ i) = max x ÎR+(v – x) Pr(vj < b-1(x) " j ¹ i) = max x ÎR+(v – x) FN-1(b-1(x))
If there is a symmetric, increasing equilibrium in a first-price auction… b(v) must solve First-order condition (b-1)’ = 1/b’x = b(v) in equilibrium so integrating from 0 to v,
So if there is a “nice” equilibrium, it must be b(v) = ò0v sd(FN-1(s)) / FN-1(v) • What is this? • Well, if a random variable y has cumulative distribution G with positive support, then ò0v s dG(s) / G(v) = E(y | y < v) • And FN-1(v) is the cumulative distribution function of the highest of N-1 independent draws from F • So if we let v1 and v2 refer to the highest and second-highest valuations in a symmetric IPV model, then b(v) = E(v2 | v1 = v)
Now here’s where it gets cool… • In the symmetric equilibrium of the second-price auction, the price paid is v2, so the seller’s expected revenue is simply E(v2) • In the symmetric, increasing equilibrium in the first-price auction (if it exists), • The bidder with the highest value wins • If the highest value is v, the winner pays E(v2 | v1 = v) • So the seller’s expected revenue is E v1 E(v2 | v1) = E(v2) • So the seller’s expected revenue is the same in both auctions!
And similarly… • In the first-price auction… • A bidder with type v expects to win with probability FN-1(v), and to pay b(v) = E(v2 | v1 = v) when he wins • So his expected payoff is FN-1(v) [ v – E(v2 | v1 = v) ] • In the second-price auction… • A bidder with type v expects to win whenever he has the highest value (v1 = v), and to pay v2 when he wins • So his expected payment, conditional on winning, is E(v2 | v1 = v) • And so his expected payoff is FN-1(v) [ v – E(v2 | v1 = v) ] • So each type of bidder gets the same expected payoff in the two auctions
This turns out not to be a fluke • This is exactly what we’ll prove more generally next class: • With independent private values, any two auctions in which, in equilibrium, • the player with the highest value wins the object, and • any player with the lowest possible type gets expected payoff of 0 will give the same expected payoff to each type of each player, and the same expected revenue to the seller • So, (a) this is pretty interesting, and (b) once we’ve proven this, we can use it to calculate equilibrium strategies much more easily
In Case We Have Time,A Few Slides on Second-Order Stochastic Dominance
When is one probability distribution less risky than another? • Two random variables X and Y with the same mean, with distributions F and G • Three conditions to consider: 1. “Every risk-averse utility maximizer prefers X to Y”, i.e., E u(X) ³ E u(Y) for every nondecreasing, concave u, or ò-¥¥ u(s) dF(s) ³ò-¥¥ u(s) dG(s) (also called SOSD) 2. “Y is a mean-preserving spread of X”, or “Y = X + noise”: $ r.v. Z s.t. Y =d X + Z, with E(Z|X) = 0 for every value of X 3. For every x,ò-¥x F(s) ds £ò-¥x G(s) ds • Rothschild-Stiglitz (1970): 1« 2 «3
What does this tell us? • Risk-averse buyers greatly impact auction design – changes equilibrium strategies – we’ll get to that in a few lectures (Maskin and Riley) • Risk-averse sellers have less impact – equilibrium strategies are the same, all that changes is seller’s valuation of different distributions of revenue • Claim. With symmetric IPV, a risk-averse seller prefers a first-price to a second-price auction
Proof: we’ll show revenue in second-price auction is MPS of revenue in first-price • Recall that revenue in a second-price auction is v2, and revenue in a first-price auction is E(v2 | v1) • Let X, Y, and Z be random variables derived from bidders’ valuations, as follows: • X = g(v1) • Z = v2 – g(v1) • Y = v2 • where g(t) = ò0ts dFN-1(s) / FN-1(t) = E(v2 | v1 = t) • Note that Y = X + Z, andE(Z | X=g(t)) = E(v2 | v1 = t) – E(v2 | v1 = t) = 0 • So Y is a mean-preserving spread of X, so any risk-averse utility maximizer prefers X to Y • But X is the revenue in the first-price auction, and Y is the revenue in the second-price auction – Q.E.D.
A cool proof SOSD º“ò-¥x F(s) ds £ò-¥x G(s) ds everywhere” • We’ll use the “extremal method” or “basis function method” • We’ll rewrite our generic (increasing concave) function u(s) as a positive sum of basis functions u(s) = ò-¥¥ w(q) h(s,q) dq with w(q) ³ 0, where these basis functions are themselves increasing and concave • Then we’ll show that X SOSD Y if and only if ò-¥¥ h(x,q) dF(x) ³ò-¥¥ h(y,q) dG(y) for all the basis functions • (“Only if” is trivial, since h(s,q) is increasing and concave; “if” just involves multiplying this inequality by w(q) and integrating over q)
A cool proof SOSD º“ò-¥x F(s) ds £ò-¥x G(s) ds everywhere” • We’ll do the special case of u twice differentiable. Our basis functions will be a constant, a linear term, and the functionsh(x,q) = min(x,q) • Claim is thatu(x) = a + bx + ò0¥ (-u’’(q)) h(x,q) dq • Note that -u’’(q) is nonnegative, since u is concave • To see the equality, integrate by parts, with db = -u’’ dq, a = h:ò a db = a b – ò b da = –h(x,q)u’(q)|q=-¥¥ – ò-¥¥ –u’(q) 1q<x dq= –xu’(¥) + constant + ò-¥x u’(q) dq • Since X and Y have the same mean, ò-¥¥ (a+bx) dF(x) =ò-¥¥ (a+by) dG(y)
A cool proof SOSD º“ò-¥x F(s) ds £ò-¥x G(s) ds everywhere” • So all that’s left is to determine when ò-¥¥ h(s,q) dF(s) ³ò-¥¥ h(s,q) dG(s) • Integrate by parts: u = h(s,q),dv = dF(s), LHS becomesh(¥,q) F(¥) – h(-¥,q) F(-¥) – ò-¥¥ F(s) hs(s,q) ds= q – 0 – ò-¥¥ F(s) 1s<q ds = q – ò-¥ q F(s) ds • Similarly, the right-hand side becomes q – ò-¥ q G(s) ds • So Es~F h(s,q) ³ Es~G h(s,q)«ò-¥ q F(s) ds £ò-¥ q G(s) ds • So X SOSD Y if and only if this holds for every q