310 likes | 727 Views
Econ 805 Advanced Micro Theory 1. Dan Quint Fall 2007 Lecture 4 – Sept 18 2007. Today: Necessary and Sufficient Conditions For Equilibrium. Problem set 1 online (due 9 a.m. Wed Oct 3); email list
E N D
Econ 805Advanced Micro Theory 1 Dan Quint Fall 2007 Lecture 4 – Sept 18 2007
Today: Necessary and Sufficient Conditions For Equilibrium • Problem set 1 online (due 9 a.m. Wed Oct 3); email list • Last lecture: integral form of the Envelope Theorem holds in equilibrium of any Independent Private Value auction where • The highest type wins the object • The lowest possible type gets expected payoff 0 • Today: necessary and sufficient conditions for a particular bidding function to be a symmetric equilibrium in such an auction • Time permitting, stochastic dominance
Today’s General Results • Consider a symmetric independent private values model of some auction, and a bid function b : T R+ • Define g(x,t) as one bidder’s expected payoff, given type t and bid x, if all the other bidders bid according to b • Under fairly broad (but not all) conditions: “everyone bidding according to b” is an equilibrium b strictly increasing and g(b(t’),t’) – g(b(t),t) = òtt’ FN-1(s) ds
With symmetric IPV, b strictly increasing implies the envelope theorem • If everyone bids according to the same bid function b, • And b is strictly increasing, • Then the highest type wins, • And so the envelope theorem holds • So what we’re really asking here is when a symmetric bid function must be strictly increasing
When must bid functions be increasing? • Equilibrium strategies are solutions to the maximization problem maxxg(x,t) • What conditions on g makes every selection x(t) from x*(t) nondecreasing? • Recall supermodularity and Topkis • If g(x,t) has increasing differences in (x,t), then the set x*(t) is increasing in t (in the strong set order) • For g differentiable, this is when ¶ 2g / ¶ x¶ t ³0 • But let t’ > t; if x* is not single-valued, this still allows some points in x*(t) to be above some points in x*(t’), so it wouldn’t rule out equilibrium strategies which are decreasing at some points
Single crossing and single crossing differences properties (Milgrom/Shannon) • A function h : T R satisfies the strict single crossing property if for every t’ > t, h(t) ³0 h(t’) > 0 (Also known as, “h crosses 0 only once, from below”) • A function g : X x T R satisfies the strict single crossing differences property if for every x’ > x, the function h(t) = g(x’,t) – g(x,t) satisfies strict single crossing • That is, g satisfies strict single crossing differences if g(x’,t) – g(x,t)³0 g(x’,t’) – g(x,t’) > 0 for every x’ > x, t’ > t • (When gt exists everywhere, a sufficient condition is for gt to be strictly increasing in x)
What single-crossing differences gives us • Theorem.* Suppose g(x,t) satisfies strict single crossing differences. Let S Í X be any subset. Let x*(t) = arg maxx Î S g(x,t), and let x(t) be any (pointwise) selection from x*(t). Then x(t) is nondecreasing in t. • Proof. Let t’ > t, x’ = x(t’) and x = x(t). • By optimality, g(x,t)³g(x’,t) and g(x’,t’)³g(x,t’) • So g(x,t) – g(x’,t)³ 0 andg(x,t’) – g(x’,t’) £ 0 • If x > x’, this violates strict single crossing differences * Milgrom (PATW) theorem 4.1, or a special case of theorem 4’ in Milgrom/Shannon 1994
Strict single-crossing differences will hold in “most” symmetric IPV auctions • Suppose b : T R+ is a symmetric equilibrium of some auction game in our general setup • Assume that the other N-1 bidders bid according to b;g(x,t) = t Pr(win | bid x) – E(pay | bid x) = t W(x) – P(x) • For x’ > x, g(x’,t) – g(x,t) = [ W(x’) – W(x) ] t – [ P(x’) – P(x) ] • When does this satisfy strict single-crossing?
When is strict single crossing satisfied byg(x’,t) – g(x,t) = [ W(x’) – W(x) ] t – [ P(x’) – P(x) ] ? • Assume W(x’)³W(x) (probability of winning nondecreasing in bid) • g(x’,t) – g(x,t) is weakly increasing in t, so if it’s strictly positive at t, it’s strictly positive at t’ > t • Need to check that if g(x’,t) – g(x,t) = 0, then g(x’,t’) – g(x,t’) > 0 • This can only fail if W(x’) = W(x) • If b has convex range, W(x’) > W(x), so strict single crossing differences holds and b must be nondecreasing (e.g.: T convex, b continuous) • If W(x’) = W(x) and P(x’) ¹ P(x)(e.g., first-price auction, since P(x) = x), then g(x’,t) – g(x,t) ¹ 0, so there’s nothing to check • But, if W(x’) = W(x) and P(x’) = P(x), then bidding x’ and x give the same expected payoff, so b(t) = x’ and b(t’) = x could happen in equilibrium • Example. A second-price auction, with values uniformly distributed over [0,1] È [2,3]. The bid function b(2) = 1, b(1) = 2, b(vi) = vi otherwise is a symmetric equilibrium. • But other than in a few weird situations, b will be nondecreasing
b will almost always be strictly increasing • Suppose b(-) were constant over some range of types [t’,t’’] • Then there is positive probability (N – 1) [ F(t’’) – F(t’) ] FN – 2(t’) of tying with one other bidder by bidding b* (plus the additional possibility of tying with multiple bidders) • Suppose you only pay if you win; let B be the expected payment, conditional on bidding b* and winning • Since t’’ > t’, either t’’ > B or B > t’, so either you strictly prefer to win at t’’ or you strictly prefer to lose at t’ • Assume that when you tie, you win with probability greater than 0 but less than 1 • Then you can strictly gain in expectation either by reducing b(t’) by a sufficiently small amount, or by raising b(t’’) by a sufficiently small amount • (In addition: when T has point mass… second-price… first-price…)
So to sum up, in “well-behaved” symmetric IPV auctions, except in very weird situations, • any symmetric equilibrium bid function will be strictly increasing, • and the envelope formula will therefore hold • Next: when are these sufficient conditions for a bid function b to be a symmetric equilibrium?
What are generally sufficient conditions for optimality in this type of problem? • A function g(x,t) satisfies the smooth single crossing differences condition if for any x’ > x and t’ > t, • g(x’,t) – g(x,t) > 0 g(x’,t’) – g(x,t’) > 0 • g(x’,t) – g(x,t) ³ 0 g(x’,t’) – g(x,t’) ³ 0 • gx(x,t) = 0 gx(x,t+d) ³ 0 ³ gx(x,t – d) for all d > 0 • Theorem. (PATW th 4.2) Suppose g(x,t) is continuously differentiable and has the smooth single crossing differences property. Let x : [0,1] R have range X’, and suppose x is the sum of a jump function and an absolutely continuous function. If • x is nondecreasing, and • the envelope formula holds: for every t, g(x(t),t) – g(x(0),0) = ò0t gt(x(s),s) ds then x(t) Î arg maxx Î X’ g(x,t) • (Note that x only guaranteed optimal over X’, not over all X)
But… • Establishing smooth single-crossing differences requires a bunch of conditions on b • We can use the payoff structure of an IPV auction to give a simpler proof • Proof is taken from Myerson (“Optimal Auctions”), which we’re doing on Thursday anyway
Claim • Theorem. Consider any auction where the highest bid gets the object. Assume the type space T has no point masses. Let b : T R+ be any function, and define g(x,t) in the usual way. If • b is strictly increasing, and • the envelope formula holds: for every t, g(b(t),t) – g(b(0),0) = ò0t FN-1(s) ds then g(b(t),t) ³ g(b(t’),t), that is, no bidder can gain by making a bid that a different type would make. If, in addition, the type space T is convex, b is continuous, and neither the highest nor the lowest type can gain by bidding outside the range of b, then everyone bidding b is an equilibrium.
Proof. • Note that when you bid b(s), you win with probability FN-1(s); let z(s) denote the expected payment you make from bidding s • Suppose a bidder had a true type of t and bid b(t’) instead of b(t) • The gain from doing this is • g(b(t’), t) – g(b(t), t) = t FN-1(t’) – z(t’) – g(b(t),t) • = (t – t’) FN-1(t’) + t’ FN-1(t’) – z(t’) – g(b(t),t) • = (t – t’) FN-1(t’) + g(x(t’),t’) – g(x(t),t) • Suppose t’ > t. By assumption, the envelope theorem holds, so • = (t – t’) FN-1(t’) + òtt’ FN-1(s) ds • = òtt’ [ FN-1(s) – FN-1(t’) ] ds • But F is increasing (weakly), so FN-1(t’)³FN-1(s) for every s in the integral, so this is (weakly) negative • Symmetric argument holds for t’ < t • So the envelope formula is exactly the condition that there is never a gain to deviating to a different type’s equilibrium bid
Proof. • All that’s left is deviations to bids outside the range of b • With T convex and b continuous, the bid distribution has convex support, so we only need to check deviations to bids above and below the range of b • Assume (for notational ease) that T = [0,T] • If some type t deviated to a bid B > b(T), his expected gain would be • g(B,t) – g(b(t),t) = [ g(B,t) – g(b(T),t) ] + [ g(b(T),t) – g(b(t),t) ] • The second term is nonpositive (another type’s bid isn’t a profitable deviation) • We also know g(x,t) = t Pr(win | bid x) – z(x) has increasing differences in x and t, so for B > b(T), if g(B,t) – g(b(T),t) > 0, g(B,T) – g(b(T),t) > 0 • So if the highest type T can’t gain by bidding above b(T), no one can • By the symmetric argument, we only need to check the lowest type’s incentive to bid below b(0) • (If b was discontinuous or T had holes, we would need to also check deviations to the “holes” in the range of b) • QED
So basically, in well-behaved symmetric IPV auctions, • b : T R+is a symmetric equilibrium if and only if • b is increasing, and • b (and the g derived from it) satisfy the envelope formula
Up next… • Recasting auctions as direct revelation mechanisms • Optimal (revenue-maximizing) auctions • Might want to take a look at the Myerson paper, or the treatment in one of the textbooks • If you don’t know mechanism design, don’t worry, we’ll go over it • Meanwhile, since there’s time…
When is one probability distribution less risky than another? • Two random variables X and Y with the same mean, with distributions F and G • Three conditions to consider: 1. “Every risk-averse utility maximizer prefers X to Y”, i.e., E u(X) ³ E u(Y) for every nondecreasing, concave u, or ò-¥¥ u(s) dF(s) ³ò-¥¥ u(s) dG(s) (also called SOSD) 2. “Y is a mean-preserving spread of X”, or “Y = X + noise”: $ r.v. Z s.t. Y =d X + Z, with E(Z|X) = 0 for every value of X 3. For every x,ò-¥x F(s) ds £ò-¥x G(s) ds • Rothschild-Stiglitz (1970): 1« 2 «3
What does this tell us? • Risk-averse buyers greatly impact auction design – changes equilibrium strategies – we’ll get to that in a few lectures (Maskin and Riley) • Risk-averse sellers have less impact – equilibrium strategies are the same, all that changes is seller’s valuation of different distributions of revenue • Claim. With symmetric IPV, a risk-averse seller prefers a first-price to a second-price auction
Proof: we’ll show revenue in second-price auction is MPS of revenue in first-price • Recall that revenue in a second-price auction is v2, and revenue in a first-price auction is E(v2 | v1) • Let X, Y, and Z be random variables derived from bidders’ valuations, as follows: • X = g(v1) • Z = v2 – g(v1) • Y = v2 • where g(t) = ò0ts dFN-1(s) / FN-1(t) = E(v2 | v1 = t) • Note that Y = X + Z, andE(Z | X=g(t)) = E(v2 | v1 = t) – E(v2 | v1 = t) = 0 • So Y is a mean-preserving spread of X, so any risk-averse utility maximizer prefers X to Y • But X is the revenue in the first-price auction, and Y is the revenue in the second-price auction – Q.E.D.
A cool proof SOSD º“ò-¥x F(s) ds £ò-¥x G(s) ds everywhere” • We’ll use the “extremal method” or “basis function method” • We’ll rewrite our generic (increasing concave) function u(s) as a positive sum of basis functions u(s) = ò-¥¥ w(q) h(s,q) dq with w(q) ³ 0, where these basis functions are themselves increasing and concave • Then we’ll show that X SOSD Y if and only if ò-¥¥ h(x,q) dF(x) ³ò-¥¥ h(y,q) dG(y) for all the basis functions • (“Only if” is trivial, since h(s,q) is increasing and concave; “if” just involves multiplying this inequality by w(q) and integrating over q)
A cool proof SOSD º“ò-¥x F(s) ds £ò-¥x G(s) ds everywhere” • We’ll do the special case of u twice differentiable. Our basis functions will be a constant, a linear term, and the functionsh(x,q) = min(x,q) • Claim is thatu(x) = a + bx + ò0¥ (-u’’(q)) h(x,q) dq • Note that -u’’(q) is nonnegative, since u is concave • To see the equality, integrate by parts, with db = -u’’ dq, a = h:ò a db = a b – ò b da = –h(x,q)u’(q)|q=-¥¥ – ò-¥¥ –u’(q) 1q<x dq= –xu’(¥) + constant + ò-¥x u’(q) dq • Since X and Y have the same mean, ò-¥¥ (a+bx) dF(x) =ò-¥¥ (a+by) dG(y)
A cool proof SOSD º“ò-¥x F(s) ds £ò-¥x G(s) ds everywhere” • So all that’s left is to determine when ò-¥¥ h(s,q) dF(s) ³ò-¥¥ h(s,q) dG(s) • Integrate by parts: u = h(s,q),dv = dF(s), LHS becomesh(¥,q) F(¥) – h(-¥,q) F(-¥) – ò-¥¥ F(s) hs(s,q) ds= q – 0 – ò-¥¥ F(s) 1s<q ds = q – ò-¥ q F(s) ds • Similarly, the right-hand side becomes q – ò-¥ q G(s) ds • So Es~F h(s,q) ³ Es~G h(s,q)«ò-¥ q F(s) ds £ò-¥ q G(s) ds • So X SOSD Y if and only if this holds for every q
When is one probability distribution “better” than another? • Two probability distributions, F and G • Ffirst-order stochastically dominatesG if ò-¥¥ u(s) dF(s) ³ò-¥¥ u(s) dG(s) for every nondecreasing function u • So anyone who’s maximizing any increasing function prefers the distribution of outcomes F to G • (Very strong condition.) • Theorem.F first-order stochastically dominates G if and only if F(x)£G(x) for every x.
Proving FOSD º “F(x)£G(x) everywhere” • Proof for differentiable u. Rewrite it using a basis consisting of step functionsdq(s) = 0 if s < q, 1 if s ³q • Up to an additive constant,u(s) = ò-¥¥ u’(q) dq(s) dq • To see this, calculateu(s’) – u(s) = ò-¥¥ u’(q) (dq(s’) – dq(s)) dq = òss’ u’(q) dq • So F FOSD G if and only if ò-¥¥dq(s) dF(s) ³ò-¥¥dq(s) dG(s) for every q
Proving FOSD º “F(x)£G(x) everywhere” • Butò-¥¥dq(s) dF(s) = Pr(s ³q) = 1 – F(q)and similarly ò-¥¥dq(s) dG(s) = 1 – G(q) • So if F(x) £G(x) for all x, Es~F u(s)³Es~G u(s) for any increasing u • “Only if” is because dq(x) is a valid increasing function of x