1 / 71

Possibility Theory and its applications: a retrospective and prospective view

Possibility Theory and its applications: a retrospective and prospective view. D. Dubois, H. Prade IRIT-CNRS, Université Paul Sabatier 31062 TOULOUSE FRANCE. Outline. Basic definitions Pioneers Qualitative possibility theory Quantitative possibility theory.

Download Presentation

Possibility Theory and its applications: a retrospective and prospective view

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. Possibility Theory and its applications: a retrospective and prospective view D. Dubois, H. Prade IRIT-CNRS, Université Paul Sabatier 31062 TOULOUSE FRANCE

  2. Outline • Basic definitions • Pioneers • Qualitative possibility theory • Quantitative possibility theory

  3. Possibility theory is an uncertainty theory devoted to the handling of incomplete information. • similar to probability theory because it is based on set-functions. • differs by the use of a pair of dual set functions (possibility and necessity measures) instead of only one. • it is not additive and makes sense on ordinal structures. The name "Theory of Possibility" was coined by Zadeh in 1978

  4. The concept of possibility • Feasibility:It is possible to do something (physical) • Plausibility: It is possible thatsomething occurs (epistemic) • Consistency : Compatible with what is known (logical) • Permission: It is allowed to do something (deontic)

  5. POSSIBILITY DISTRIBUTIONS(uncertainty) • S: frame of discernment (set of "states of the world") • x : ill-known description of the current state of affairs taking its value on S • L: Plausibility scale: totally ordered set of plausibility levels ([0,1], finite chain, integers,...) • A possibility distribution πx attached to x is a mapping from S to L : s, πx(s)  L, such that s, πx(s) = 1 (normalization) • Conventions: πx(s) = 0 iff x = s is impossible, totally excluded πx(s) = 1 iff x = s is normal, fully plausible, unsurprizing

  6. EXAMPLE : x = AGE OF PRESIDENT • If I do not know the age of the president, I may have statistics on presidents ages… but generally not, or they may be irrelevant. • partial ignorance : • 70 ≤ x ≤ 80 (sets,intervals) a uniform possibility distribution π(x) = 1 x  [70, 80] = 0 otherwise • partial ignorance with preferences : May have reasons to believe that72 > 71  73 > 70  74 > 75 > 76 > 77

  7. EXAMPLE : x = AGE OF PRESIDENT • Linguistic information described by fuzzy sets: “ he is old ” : π = µOLD • If I bet on president's age: I may come up with a subjective probability ! But this result is enforced by the setting of exchangeable bets (Dutch book argument). Actual information is often poorer.

  8. A possibility distribution is the representation of a state of knowledge: a description of how we think the state of affairs is. • π' more specific than π in the wide sense if and only if π' ≤ π In other words: any value possible for π' should be at least as possible for π that is, π' is more informative than π • COMPLETE KNOWLEDGE : The most specific ones • π(s0) = 1 ; π(s) = 0 otherwise • IGNORANCE : π(s) = 1,  s  S

  9. POSSIBILITY AND NECESSITY OF AN EVENT • A possibility distribution on S (the normal values of x) • an event A How confident are we that x  A  S ? • (A) = maxuAπ(s); The degree of possibility that x  A • N(A) = 1 – (Ac)=min uA 1 – π(s) The degree of certainty (necessity) that x  A

  10. Comparing the value of a quantity x to a threshold when the value of x is only known to belong to an interval [a, b]. • In this example, the available knowledge is modeled by p(x) = 1 if  x  [a, b], 0 otherwise. • Proposition p = "x > " to be checked • i) a > : then x >  is certainly true : N(x >  ) = P(x >  ) = 1. • ii) b < : then x >  is certainly false ; N(x >  ) = P(x >  ) = 0. • iii) a ≤  ≤ b: then x >  is possibly true or false; N(x >  ) = 0; P(x >  ) = 1.

  11. Basic properties (A) = to what extent at least one element in A is consistent with π (= possible) N(A) = 1 – (Ac) = to what extent no element outside A is possible = to what extent π implies A (A  B) = max((A), (B)); N(A  B) = min(N(A), N(B)). Mind that most of the time : (A  B) < min((A), (B)); N(A B) > max(N(A), N(B) Corollary N(A) > 0 (A) = 1

  12. Pioneers of possibility theory • In the 1950’s, G.L.S. Shackle called "degree of potential surprize" of an event its degree of impossibility. • Potential surprize is valued on a disbelief scale, namely a positive interval of the form [0, y*], where y* denotes the absolute rejection of the event to which it is assigned. • The degree of surprize of an event is the degree of surprize of its least surprizing realization. • He introduces a notion of conditional possibility

  13. Pioneers of possibility theory • In his 1973 book, the philosopherDavid Lewisconsiders a relation between possible worlds he calls "comparative possibility". • He relates this concept of possibility to a notion of similarity between possible worlds for defining the truth conditions of counterfactual statements. • for events A, B, C, A B C  A  C  B. • The ones and only ordinal counterparts to possibility measures

  14. Pioneers of possibility theory • The philosopherL. J. Cohenconsidered the problem of legal reasoning (1977). • "Baconian probabilities" understood as degrees of provability. • It is hard to prove someone guilty at the court of law by means of pure statistical arguments. • A hypothesis and its negation cannot both have positive "provability" • Such degrees of provability coincide with necessity measures.

  15. Pioneers of possibility theory • Zadeh(1978) proposed an interpretation of membership functions of fuzzy sets as possibility distributions encoding flexible constraints induced by natural language statements. • relationship between possibility and probability: what is probable must preliminarily be possible. • refers to the idea of graded feasibility ("degrees of ease") rather than to the epistemic notion of plausibility. • the key axiom of "maxitivity" for possibility measures is highlighted (also for fuzzy events).

  16. Qualitative vs. quantitative possibility theories • Qualitative: • comparative: A complete pre-ordering ≥πon U A well-ordered partition of U: E1 > E2 > … > En • absolute: πx(s)  L = finite chain, complete lattice... • Quantitative: πx(s)  [0, 1], integers... One must indicate where the numbers come from. All theories agree on the fundamental maxitivity axiom(A  B) = max((A), (B)) Theories diverge on the conditioning operation

  17. Ordinal possibilistic conditioning • A Bayesian-like equation: A) = min(A), ) A) is the maximal solution to this equation. (B | A) = 1 if A, B ≠ Ø, (A) = (A  B) > 0 = (A  B) if (A) > (A  B) N(B | A) = 1 – (Bc| A) • Independence (B | A) = (B) impliesA) = min(), ) Not the converse!!!!

  18. QUALITATIVE POSSIBILISTIC REASONING • The set of states of affairs is partitioned via π into a totally ordered set of clusters of equally plausible states E1 (normal worlds) > E2 >... En+1 (impossible worlds) • ASSUMPTION: the current situation is normal. By default the state of affairs is in E1 • N(A) > 0 iff P(A) > P(Ac) iff A is true in all the normal situations Then, A is accepted as an expected truth • Accepted events are closed under deduction

  19. A CALCULUS OF PLAUSIBLE INFERENCE (B) ≥(C) means « Comparing propositions on the basis of their most normal models » • ASSUMPTION for computing (B): the current situation is the most normal where B is true. • PLAUSIBLE REASONING = “ reasoning as if the current situation were normal” and jumping to accepted conclusions obtained from the normality assumption. • DIFFERENT FROM PROBABILISTIC REASONING BASED ON AVERAGING

  20. ACCEPTANCE IS DEFEASIBLE • If B is learned to be true, then the normal situations become the most plausible ones in B, and the accepted beliefs are revised accordingly • Accepting A in the context where B is true: • P(AB) > P(Ac B) iff N(A | B) > 0(conditioning) • One may have N(A) > 0 , N(Ac | B) > 0 : non-monotony

  21. PLAUSIBLE INFERENCE WITH A POSSIBILITY DISTRIBUTION Given a non-dogmatic possibility distribution π on S (π(s) > 0, s) Propositions A, and B • A |=πB iff (A  B) > (A Bc) It means that B is true in the most plausible worlds where A is true • This is a form of inference first proposed by Shoham in nonmonotonic reasoning

  22. PLAUSIBLE INFERENCE WITH A POSSIBILITY DISTRIBUTION (in A)

  23. Exa mple (continued) • Pieces of knowledge like ∆ = {b f, p  b, p  ¬f} can be expressed by constraints (b  f) > ( b ¬f) (p  b) > (p  ¬b) (p  ¬f) > (p  f) • the minimally specific π* ranks normal situations first: ¬p  b  f, ¬p ¬b • then abnormal situations: ¬f  b • Last, totally absurd situations f  p , ¬b p

  24. Example (back to possibilistic logic)  = material implication • Ranking of rules: b f has less priority that others according to p*: N*(b f ) = N*(p  b) > N*(b f) • Possibilistic base : K = {(b f ), (p  b), (p  ¬f)}, with  < 

  25. Applications of qualitative possibility theory • Exception-tolerant Reasoning in rule bases • Belief revision and inconsistency handling in deductive knowledge bases • Handling priority in constraint-based reasoning • Decision-making under uncertainty with qualitative criteria (scheduling) • Abductive reasoning for diagnosis under poor causal knowledge (satellite faults, car engine test-benches)

  26. ABSOLUTE APPROACH TO QUALITATIVE DECISION • A set of states S; • A set of consequences X. • A decision = a mapping f from S to X • f(s) is the consequence of decision f when the state is known to be s. • Problem : rank-order the set of decisions in XS when the state is ill-known and there is a utility function on X. • This is SAVAGE framework.

  27. ABSOLUTE APPROACH TO QUALITATIVE DECISION • Uncertainty on states is possibilistic a function π: S  L L is a totally ordered plausibility scale • Preference on consequences: a qualitative utility function µ: X  U • µ(x) = 0 totally rejected consequence • µ(y) > µ(x) y preferred to x • µ(x) = 1 preferred consequence

  28. Possibilistic decision criteria • Qualitative pessimistic utility (Whalen): UPES(f) = minsS max(n(π(s)), µ(f(s))) where n is the order-reversing map of V • Low utility : plausible state with bad consequences • Qualitative optimistic utility (Yager): UOPT(f) = maxsS min(π(s), µ(f(s))) • High utility: plausible states with good consequences

  29. The pessimistic and optimistic utilities are well-known fuzzy pattern-matching indices • in fuzzy expert systems: • µ = membership function of rule condition • π = imprecision of input fact • in fuzzy databases • µ = membership function of query • π = distribution of stored imprecise data • in pattern recognition • µ = membership function of attribute template • π = distribution of an ill-known object attribute

  30. Assumption: plausibility and preference scales L and U are commensurate • There exists a common scale V that contains both L and U, so that confidence and uncertainty levels can be compared. • (certainty equivalent of a lottery) • If only a subset E of plausible states is known • π = E • UPES(f) = minsE µ(f(s)) (utility of the worst consequence in E) criterion of Wald under ignorance • UOPT(f)= maxsE µ(f(s))

  31. On a linear state space

  32. Pessimistic qualitative utility of binary acts xAy, with µ(x) > µ(y): • xAy (s) = x if A occurs = y if its complement Ac occurs UPES(xAy) = median {µ(x), N(A), µ(y)} • Interpretation: If the agent is sure enough of A, it is as if the consequence is x: UPES(f) = µF(x) If he is not sure about A it is as if the consequence is y: UPES(f) = µF(y) Otherwise, utility reflects certainty: UPES(f) = N(A) • WITH UOPT(f) : replace N(A) by (A)

  33. Representation theorem for pessimistic possibilistic criteria • Suppose the preference relation a on acts obeys the following properties: • (XS, a) is a complete preorder. • there are two acts such that f a g. •  A, f, x, y constant,x  a y  xAfyAf • if f >a h and g >a h imply f g >a h • if x is constant, h >a x and h >a g imply h >a xg then there exists a finite chain L, an L-valued necessity measure on S and an L-valued utility function u, such thata is representable by the pessimistic possibilistic criterion UPES(f).

  34. Merits and limitations of qualitative decision theory • Provides a foundation for possibility theory • Possibility theory is justified by observing how a decision-maker ranks acts • Applies to one-shot decisions (no compensations/ accumulation effects in repeated decision steps) • Presupposes that consecutive qualitative value levels are distant from each other (negligibility effects)

  35. Quantitative possibility theory • Membership functions of fuzzy sets • Natural language descriptions pertaining to numerical universes (fuzzy numbers) • Results of fuzzy clustering Semantics: metrics, proximity to prototypes • Upper probability bound • Random experiments with imprecise outcomes • Consonant approximations of convex probability sets Semantics: frequentist, subjectivist (gambles)...

  36. Quantitative possibility theory • Orders of magnitude of very small probabilities degrees of impossibility k(A) ranging on integers k(A) = n iff P(A) = en • Likelihood functions (P(A| x), where x varies) behave like possibility distributions P(A| B) ≤ maxx B P(A| x)

  37. POSSIBILITY AS UPPER PROBABILITY • Given a numerical possibility distribution p, define P(p) = {Probabilities P | P(A) ≤ (A) for all A} • Then, generally it holds that (A) = sup {P(A) | P P(p)} N(A) = inf {P(A) | P P(p)} • So p is a faithful representation of a family of probability measures.

  38. From confidence sets to possibility distributions Consider a nested family of sets E1E2 …  En a set of positive numbers a1 …an in [0, 1] and the family of probability functions P = {P | P(Ei) ≥ ai for all i}. Pis always representable by means of a possibility measure. Its possibility distribution is precisely πx = mini max(µEi, 1 – ai)

  39. Random set view • Let mi = i – i+1 then m1 +… + mn = 1 A basic probability assignment (SHAFER) • π(s) = ∑i: sAi mi (one point-coverage function) • Only in the consonant case can m be recalculated from π

  40. CONDITIONAL POSSIBILITY MEASURES • A Coxian axiom(A C) = (A |C)*(C), with * = product Then: (A |C) = (A C)/ (C) N(A|C) = 1 – (Ac | C) Dempster rule of conditioning (preserves s-maxitivity) For the revision of possibility distributions: minimal change of  when N(C) = 1. It improves the state of information (reduction of focal elements)

  41. Bayesian possibilistic conditioning (A |b C) = sup{P(A|C), P ≤ , P(C) > 0} N(A |b C) = inf{P(A|C), P ≤ , P(C) > 0} It is still a possibility measure π(s |b C) = π(s)max(1, 1/( π(s) + N(C))) It can be shownthat: (A |b C) = (A C)/ ((A C) + N(AcC)) N(A|bC) = N(A C) / (N(A C) + P(AcC)) = 1 – (Ac |b C) For inference from generic knowledge based on observations

  42. Possibility-Probability transformations • Why ? • fusion of heterogeneous data • decision-making : betting according to a possibility distribution leads to probability. • Extraction of a representative value • Simplified non-parametric imprecise probabilistic models

  43. Elementary forms of probability-possibility transformations exist for a long time • POSS PROB: Laplace indifference principle  “ All that is equipossible is equiprobable ” = changing a uniform possibility distribution into a uniform probability distribution • PROB POSS: Confidence intervals Replacing a probability distribution by an interval A with a confidence level c. • It defines a possibility distribution • π(x) = 1 if x  A, = 1 – c if x  A

  44. Possibility-Probability transformations : BASIC PRINCIPLES • Possibility probability consistency: P ≤  • Preserving the ordering of events : P(A) ≥ P(B) (A) ≥ (B) or elementary events only(x) > (x') if and only if p(x) > p(x')(orderpreservation) • Informational criteria: from  to P: Preservation of symmetries (Shapley value rather than maximal entropy) from P to : optimize information content (Maximization or minimisation of specificity

  45. From OBJECTIVE probability to possibility : • Rationale : given a probability p, try and preserve as much information as possible • Select a most specific element of the set PI(P) = {:  ≥ P} of possibility measures dominating P such that  (x) >  (x') iff p(x) > p(x') • may be weakened into : p(x) > p(x')implies (x) >  (x') • The result is i = j=i,…n pi (case of no ties)

  46. From probability to possibility : Continuous case • The possibility distribution  obtained by transforming p encodes then family of confidence intervals around the mode of p. • The a-cut of  is the (1- a)-confidence interval of p • The optimal symmetric transform of the uniform probability distribution is the triangular fuzzy number • The symmetric triangular fuzzy number (STFN) is a covering approximation of any probability with unimodal symmetric density p with the same mode. • In other words the a-cut of a STFN contains the (1- a)-confidence interval of any such p.

  47. From probability to possibility : Continuous case • IL = {x, p(x) ≥ } =[aL, aL+ L] is the interval of length L with maximal probability • The most specific possibility distribution dominating p is π such that L > 0, π(aL) = π(aL+ L) = 1 – P(IL). b

  48. Possibilistic view of probabilistic inequalities • Chebyshev inequality defines a possibility distribution that dominates any density with given mean and variance. • The symmetric triangular fuzzy number (STFN) defines a possibility distribution that optimally dominates anysymmetric density with given mode and bounded support.

  49. From possibility to probability • Idea (Kaufmann, Yager, Chanas): • Pick a number  in [0, 1] at random • Pick an element at random in the -cut of π. a generalized Laplacean indifference principle : change alpha-cuts into uniform probability distributions. • Rationale : minimise arbitrariness by preserving the symmetry properties of the representation. • The resulting probability distribution is: • The centre of gravity of the polyhedron P(p) • The pignistic transformation of belief functions (Smets) • The Shapley value of the unanimity game N in game theory.

  50. SUBJECTIVE POSSIBILITY DISTRIBUTIONS • Starting point : exploit the betting approach to subjective probability • A critique: The agent is forced to be additive by the rules of exchangeable bets. • For instance, the agent provides a uniform probability distribution on a finite set whether (s)he knows nothing about the concerned phenomenon, or if (s)he knows the concerned phenomenon is purely random. • Idea : It is assumed that a subjective probability supplied by an agent is only a trace of the agent's belief.

More Related