1 / 33

Wordfulness for Neophytes Putting jurisprudence to work to address pedagogic challenges

Explore the pedagogical challenges in law education and the role of jurisprudence in addressing them. This thought-provoking play by Max Weaver delves into the clash between common law and certainty-seeking neophytes.

mgage
Download Presentation

Wordfulness for Neophytes Putting jurisprudence to work to address pedagogic challenges

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. Wordfulness for NeophytesPutting jurisprudence to work to address pedagogic challenges Max Weaver Visiting Professor | Law Division | London South Bank University

  2. NOW You’ve seen: Wordfulness Jurisprudence and the Pedagogical Challenge A Word Play by Max Weaver

  3. The Pedagogical Challenge • ‘The limits of a student’s language are the limits of that student’s world’ • Adapted from Wittgenstein in the Tractatus 5.62

  4. Cast in order of ‘appearance’ • A neophyte law student, UCAS casting imminent • Karl Llewellyn, played by his spirit • Santa Claus, played by a hologram • Mrs Beeton, played by various law teachers • and Ernest Weinrib as himself • Other parts are played by living and deceased members of the legal, jurisprudential and philosophical communities

  5. Armchair Hypothesis 1 BUT cultural cognitive clash with common law method’s mix of • change and •predictability ‘One click’ culture Here’s our neophyte law student ‘Taught to the test’ A ‘customer’ buying outcomes

  6. Armchair Hypothesis 2 • The ‘thirst for certainty’ imports a form of ‘philosophical realism’ • an expectation that legal concepts have a mind-independent existence • Cf. JL Austin’s ‘moderate-sized specimens of dry goods’ • But we should disappoint our certainty-seeking neophyte • ‘Jurisprudence’ should be engaged—and engaging

  7. Cultural Cognitive Clash Unpacked Our neophyte is conditioned emotionally and intellectually to ‘expect’ : • clear separation of law-application from law-making • certainty, predictability • fixed and precise meanings of words • OR AT LEAST definite core of meaning modest interpretational penumbra Whereas: • Common law is judge-made • changes incrementally, with • occasional more radical interventions • Usage determines meaning • interpretation can extend to the whole concept • often no hard line between ‘core’ and ‘penumbra’

  8. American legal realism’ is fundamentally different • Legal concepts (e.g. ‘negligence’, intention’, ‘contract’) are mind-dependent • investigate the minds involved • the common law is judge-made—and changes • evaluate laws by their social effects • legal changes lag behind social changes—mostly • rules not always the best predictors of what courts will do [Based on Karl Llewellyn, ‘Some Realism about Realism’ (1931) 44 Harvard Law Review 1222, 1234-1238]

  9. Armchair hypothesis 3 • Law teachers indulge neophytes’ thirst for certainty much as parents teach the very young about Santa Claus or the Tooth Fairy • Choosing ‘formation of contract’ as a first common law topic lends a mechanistic tone • A ‘Mrs Beeton approach’ is introduced, unless great care taken about to policy aspects • Being pre-conditioned, neophytes • warm to the mechanistic aspects • tend to marginalise the subtler policy points • Of course, no law teacher actually believes in Santa Claus • although some might well be described as ‘doctrinalists’

  10. Weinrib: a paradigmatic doctrinalist • ‘[T]he notion of right and correlative duty would be undone by the non-correlative conception of the content of those rights as being based on welfare.’ • Ernest Weinrib, J. Corrective Justice (Oxford University Press, 2012) Kindle Edition, 22 • Excludes ‘deep pocket’ cases from proper ‘private law’ • (e.g.) Nettleship v. Weston • (e.g.) ‘thin skull’ cases • vicarious liability

  11. Confronting Santa Syndrome • To avoid filling the world with ‘Santa-believing adults’, parents will: • refuse to teach them Santa • begin as we mean to go on • teach them Santa but break Santa’s unreality gently • assume offspring will eventually learn the news from others

  12. Armchair hypotheses 4 (and 5) • I opt for ‘begin as you mean to go on’ • Hypothesis 4 is an important condition precedent: • Most neophyte law students have the intellectual equipment to cope with uncertainty—our problem is to overcome their emotionally entrenched pre-conditioning • Not yet tested empirically. • Assuming Hypothesis 4 is valid, Hypothesis 5 sets out three distinctions that might overcome neophytes’ pre-conditioning

  13. Armchair hypothesis 5: three useful distinctions Conclusory Verdicts • Motivations, Reasons and Justifications This notion gets sub-divided later • Factive (‘is’) (empirical) Verdicts • Normative (‘ought’) Verdicts • ‘Incontestable’ Concepts • ‘Contestable’ Concepts

  14. Armchair hypothesis 5: First Distinction Conclusory Verdicts • Motivations, Reasons and Justifications

  15. Verdicts ‘just are’ • Verdicts are conclusions • Verdicts are not motivations • Verdicts are not explanations • Verdicts are not justifications

  16. ‘Giving Verdicts’ is what judges are for • Verdict 1: ‘D is not liable to C in negligence’ • Obviously verdictive • Lacks any explanation or justification • Verdict 2: Because ‘there is no duty of care’ • Looks like, and is, a formal justification • But it is itself a ‘verdict’—and we must ask how that verdict • arose, and • is justified • Verdict 3: Because ‘there is insufficient proximity between C and D’ • Looks like, and is, a formal ‘justification’ • But it is itself a ‘verdict’—and we must ask how that verdict • arose, and • is justified Our neophyte law student is conditioned to stop at Verdict 2 We might despair of those who stop at Verdict 1 Note that open-textured words appear, in this example, only at Verdict 3 Maybe policy reasoning and value-judgements are most likely to be implicated at a stage that involves open-textured justifications Points forward to the third distinction: incontestable from contestable (and, sometimes contested)

  17. Contract model • Verdict 1: ‘C is liable to D in contract’ • Obviously verdictive but lacks any explanation or justification • Verdict 2: ‘there is agreement, consideration and an intention to create legal relations’ • Looks like, and is, a formal ‘justification’ , but it is itself a ‘verdict’—and we must ask how that verdictarose, and is justified • Whether there is consideration and/or intention to create legal relations might well involve value-judgements • Where neither precedent nor social consensus overwhelms: • judges have some ‘wiggle room’ • distinctive features of case-circumstances (call these ‘factors’) will be weighed and felt-fairness of consequences will matter (‘American Realism’)

  18. Armchair hypothesis 5: Second Distinction • Factive (‘is’) (empirical) Verdicts • Normative (‘ought’) Verdicts

  19. ‘What is the case?’ is factive and falsifiable • Norms are not falsifiable • But norms are contestable • unless composed entirely of quasi-mathematically certain concepts (‘parking meter rules’)

  20. Fact-sensitivity • Recognises that the law under consideration includes a fact-sensitivenormative concept • That concept in not mind-independent • But ‘fact-sensitive concepts’ are regarded as contestable/interpretive • Contested and applied in the light of past, present and future • Mind-dependent

  21. Fact-finding is not mind-independent • Which evidence to believe? • Choosing operative or proximate cause from the numerous causae sine qua non • Even when trying simply to explain what happened • Determining states of mind • Intention to act • Intention to cause consequences • Which consequences? • Intention to proceed with reckless disregard for consequences deemed actually foreseen • Determining ‘motive’—or ‘psychological causation’

  22. But is there ‘one’ ‘real’ meaning? On to our third distinction! A trap for neophytes • Judges sometimes use ostensibly factive language when considering a normative problem • (e.g.) ‘foreseeable’ (a falsifiable factive ‘is’) for ‘reasonably foreseeable’ (a standard setting ‘ought’)

  23. Armchair hypothesis 5: Third Distinction • ‘Incontestable’ Concepts • ‘Contestable’ Concepts

  24. Incontestable from Contestable This is INCONTESTABLY a ‘triangle’ But ‘triangularity’ is CONTESTABLE

  25. Incontestables: ‘Parking Meter’ Rules • Time and space are incontestable components of the rule • The bay delineates the space and the meter records the time • CCTV can record ‘presence

  26. But is this car ‘present’ at the instant the meter expires? Just a modest interpretive penumbra around the certain core

  27. Conjugating Contestation • Call the kind of contestation in our parking meter case ‘penumbral contestation’ • However, ‘non-penumbral contestation’ or ‘whole-concept contestation’ is commonplace • but likely under-appreciated by neophytes • Several examples in the full paper • Just two are sketched here

  28. L'Hommage à Rumsfeld • ‘Incontestable’ Concepts • ‘Contestable’ Concepts Easily confused • ‘Uncontested-Contestables’ • ‘Contested-Contestables’

  29. This line will not often be straight Consensus & Contest Consensus declines ~ 100%consensus ~ 100%consensus So too,this line Incontestable quasi-mathematical concepts Contestableconcept BUT uncontested Contestable concept increasingly contested

  30. Example 1: Consideration: Change; Entrenchment; Workarounds Advent of Legal ‘Science’ Rise of economic individualism Advent of welfarism Other concepts developed to circumvent consideration’s rigidity 1859 ‘Self Help’ published Consideration = a good reason to enforce a promise • Consideration  an essential ‘Mrs Beeton=style’ ingredient of ~all enforceable contracts. • Consideration  a ‘something’ that must move from the promisee. > 1770 < ~ 1942 < 1942 Beveridge Report 1826 UCL Law 1976 Liverpool v. Irwin 1879 Anson1st edn 1778 Rannv. Hughes

  31. Example 2: Vicarious Liability: Enduring; Expansion/Supplementation Cassidy v. MoH [1951] ‘akin to employment’… Christian Brothers [2012] Armes v. Notts. CC [2017] Advent of Legal ‘Science’ Rise of economic individualism Realisation of abuse issues Advent of welfarism ‘Deep pockets’ found to compensate victims Rise of ‘expert ‘ employees THEN of more complex business structures etc. 1859 ‘Self Help’ published Lister v. Hesley Hall Ltd [2001] Mohamud v. WM Morrison Supermarkets [2016] Masters’ liability Eventually justified by control/agency reasoning:  ‘employment’  in the course of… Masters often liable for their servants’ torts > 1770 < ~ 1942 ~2000< 1942 Beveridge Report 1860 Addison on Torts 1826 UCL Law 1942 NHS 1798 Hern v. Nichols

  32. Pedagogic Implications • Assuming my three distinctions matter: • Santa Claus has to go • Gradual induction into the distinctions? • Introduce (opportunistically) in substantive curriculum? (intuitive preference) • Some Suggested Methods • Reading • Writing • Précis brings these skills together • Mooting—entails analysis, argument, spotting ambiguity, finding weaknesses, counter-argument • Clinic—entails finding facts, finding law, devising strategy, anticipating counter arguments • Testing and feedback • A long way from reliance on ‘foundational’ doctrinal exposition alone

  33. Max Weaver Visiting Professor | Law Division | London South Bank University

More Related