460 likes | 723 Views
Voter Turnout. Overview. Recap the “Paradox” of Voting Incentives and Voter Turnout Voter Mobilization. The Paradox of Voting. Given standard assumptions on Expected Utility , voting is rarely a rational action.
E N D
Overview • Recap the “Paradox” of Voting • Incentives and Voter Turnout • Voter Mobilization
The Paradox of Voting • Given standard assumptions on Expected Utility, voting is rarely a rational action. • For any individual, x, voting is rational if and only if x’s vote will either break a tie leading to her preferred candidate’s winning or creating a tie so her preferred candidate does not lose • As the pool of potential voters increases, the probablility of either of these situations decreases dramatically
Paradox of Voting • We formalized this insight this way: ΔP * B > c ΔP = the change my vote makes in the prospects of victory for my prefered candidate B = the difference in the benefits I receive when my preferred candidate wins or loses c = costs of voting back
Paradox of Voting • We ended class by noting that people do in fact vote, so either there are millions of irrational people out there, or we need to refine the model • That is, there must be some extra benefit to voting such that: ΔP * B + D > c D = extra consumption benefits of voting not connected to the result of the vote
Pardox of Voting • And we further noted, that that explanation is not terribly helpful until or unless we can provide some content for D. • That is, we can’t simply say people vote because they like to vote. • We need to uncover why they like to vote even when the prospects of making a difference are slim to zero
Incentives and Voter Turnout • One possible understanding of D is that we omitted to include the group benefits of voting • That is, if my vote helps advance the interests of a group that I support, then maybe I should vote
Incentives and Voter Turnout • Suppose we have two members of group, Bill and Hillary, and the group supports a particular candidate (e.g, Obama over McCain) • Further suppose that the preferred candidate needs the group’s support in order to win
Incentives and Voter Turnout • Further suppose the following conditions: • Assume the group’s preferred candidate, Obama, will lose by a single vote if neither of our two voters votes • That means that if both vote, then Obama wins and if one votes it’s a tie
Incentives and Voter Turnout • Drawing on the Expected Utility idea we discussed earlier, we can put some numbers on the various scenarios: • If Obama wins, each will receive 100 utils • If McCain wins, each will recieve 25 utils • The utility difference (the B term above) would then be 100 - 25 = 75 • If it’s a tie, then they would expect to get 100 util half the time, and 25 the other half, or 100 (.5) + 25 (.5) = 62.5 utils
Incentives and Voter Turnout • But remember, we need to include the costs of voting, c, which we’ll set at 50 utils • We can now contstruct a payoff matrix to help us determine what Bill and Hillary should do:
Incentives and Voter Turnout Hillary’s Choices Don’t Vote Vote for Obama Vote for Obama 50, 50 12.5, 62.5 Bill’s Choices 62.5, 12.5 25, 25 Don’t Vote
Note that this is a classic prisoners’ dilemma Neither Bill nor Hillary has incentive to vote The two will have difficulty acting collectively to elect Obama Incentives and Voter Turnout
Incentives and Voter Turnout • Even though as a group they have the chance to influence the election to their preferred outcome (Obama), each individual voter has strong incentive to free ride on the actions of others • Upshot would be McCain elected.
Incentives and Voter Turnout • Which means in order to get voters to vote we need to transform the payoff matrix so that we are no longer in the prisoners’ dilemma • We need to provide other incentives for people to vote beyond the possibility of affecting the outcome
Mobilization • One way is to provide private selective incentives (PSI) • PSI is an extra benefit, privately defined, that is received by the individual voter • For instance, suppose the local organizers provide a free turkey to Bill and Hillary if they vote
Mobilization • Assume that the turkey is worth 25 utils to each, then the new payoff for Bill and Hillary would look like
Hillary’s Choices 75, 75 37.5, 62.5 Bill’s Choices 62.5, 37.5 25, 25
Note that in this case, the Nash equilibrium is for both Bill and Hillary to vote • So, is PSI the means to achieve higher voter turnout?
Mobilization • Not really, since we need to be wary of bribery and vote selling • PSI are legal only if the goods in question are available independent or regardless of the vote • And if that’s the case, we’re right back in the prisoner’s dilemma situation • What to do?
Mobilization • Social Selective Incentives (SSI) defined as the utility that Bill and Hillary receive from acting together as a group in a social situation
Hillary’s Choices 75, 75 12.5, 62.5 Bill’s Choices 62.5, 12.5 50, 50
Mobilization • Note that this is not a prisoners’ dilemma, but it is different from the last game we had • Here, we have not one but two Nash equilibria (both vote or neither vote) • The issue here, then, is to coordinate the group of voters on the voting equilibrium rather than the nonvoting one
Mobilization • Factors that contribute: family and peer groups • “Purposive” Benefits • Incentives that identify the benefits to the individual of the benefits of the group • That is,individuals come to equate the group benefits with their individual benefits
Mobilization • Formalizing this dynamic we get: ∆Pg * Bg > cg Where: ∆P = the effect of mobilizing groups of voters on the election outcome B = the difference in group benefits if the preferred candidate wins c = is the cost to the group of mobilization
Mobilization • Note that, for the group, the effect of mobilizing on the election can be as large as the benefits can be • That means benefits may outweigh the costs of mobilizing
Mobilization • Notice, too, that as the costs of voting for individuals increases, turnout decreases (mobilization becomes more difficult as costs rise) • Likewise, if voters are mobilized by groups whose preferences are the same as theirs, we find a positive relationship between turnout and both the investments of voting and the probability that an election is close
Mobilization • But what happens if the group mobilizing voters and the voter’s investment-movitated choice differ? • We have 2 types of mobilization forces: • mobilization of benefit seeking groups • mobilization of officer seeking groups
Mobilization • The first (benefit seeking groups) use the ability to mobilize its memberships to deliver votes for benefit seeking groups • examples: NOW, Focus on the Family, labor organizations, NAACP, etc. • Expectation is that this electoral help will translate into policies favored by the group • Mobilization based on selective incentives of group benefits.
Mobilization • Office seeking groups mobilize in voters committed to the idea of electing members of the group and act accordingly • examples: political parties
Mobilization • Note as Morton points out: “If voters are not mobilized by groups seeking policy or benefit motivations...but are instead motivated [by private consumptive benefits doled out by office seeking groups] then office-seeking groups have less reason to respond to them.” • In other words, the group, although mobilized to vote, will have little tangible rewards to show as a group for their effort.
Next Week • Candidates, Primaries, and Divergence • How did we end up with Obama and McCain as the nominees?
Don’t Cooperate Cooperate 3 , 3 1 , 4 Don’t Cooperate Cooperate 4 , 1 2 , 2 Prisoners’ Dilemma
Prisoners’ Dilemma • Symbolic Form: • We’re in a Prisoner’s Dilemma situation whenever: T > R > P > S Temptation to defect > Rewards of Cooperation Rewards > Punishment for Not Cooperating Punishment > Sucker’s Payoff
Prisoners’ Dilemma • Note that even if we start at the cooperative outcome, that outcome is not stable • Each player can improve his/her position by adopting a different strategy
Don’t Cooperate Cooperate 3 , 3 1 , 4 Don’t Cooperate Cooperate 4 , 1 2 , 2 back Prisoners’ Dilemma
Prisoners’ Dilemma • But since both players have changed strategy we end up at the non-cooperative outcome, where both players are worse off than if they had chosen to cooperate
Don’t Cooperate Cooperate 3 , 3 1 , 4 Don’t Cooperate Cooperate 4 , 1 2 , 2 Prisoners’ Dilemma
Prisoners’ Dilemma • And, as we noted, this non-cooperative outcome is also a Nash equilibrium outcome; • Neither player has any incentive to change strategy since whoever changes will do immediately worse by making the move
Don’t Cooperate Cooperate 3 , 3 1 , 4 Don’t Cooperate Cooperate 4 , 1 2 , 2 Prisoners’ Dilemma
PD & Interest Group • If a “collective good” is involved, individuals have little incentive to work towards achieving that good. • Makes sense for others to do the work and sit back and reap the benefits of their labor • But if that’s the case, then no one will do the work and the collective benefit won’t be delivered back