270 likes | 526 Views
?Does David Velleman's theory of action provide an adequate account of reasons for action?". Introduction. GOOD. THE. David Velleman's theory of action proposes that reasons for action are considerations in light of which an action makes sense to the person for whom they are reasons. Reasons here
E N D
1. GOOD Essay Examples
2. “Does David Velleman’s theory of action provide an adequate account of reasons for action?”
3. Introduction
4. Concise
Explains how the question will be answered
Gives general structure of the essay
Gives general content of the essay
No unnecessary information
No undefined technical terms
5. Largely irrelevant to the question
Undefined technical terms
Doesn’t get to the point
No clear indication of how the question will be answered/the essay will be structured.
6. Irrelevant material
Weak or no connection with the question
Weak or ambiguous claims
No indication that the question has been understood
No indication of how the question will be answered
7. Body
8. Clear and concise
Well referenced
Paraphrases and shows understanding of quoted material
Puts argument into a form that is easy to read and understand
9.
Generally unclear
Not clear the author understands the material.
No explanation of some important claims
Poor referencing
Doesn’t flow well
10. No paragraphs
Very unclear
Material not specifically directed at the question
No references
No clear argument: no explanation of how the problems raised are actually problems for the theory.
11. Conclusion
12. Concise
Ties the essay together: Explains how the argument leads to the conclusion
Clearly answers the question
13. Unclear
Very weak conclusion
Fence sitting. Does not answer the question.
Tries to say too much and so ends up saying very little of value.
14. Unclear
New material introduced in conclusion
Incorrect usage of technical terms
Not clear whether author has understood the question, or material, at all
15. Structure
16. Doesn’t try to tackle too much
Three main points
Argues for one side: will answer the question one way or the other
17.
Far too much material
No room for good discussion/argument of any of the topics
For/against structure doesn’t flow well
Ends up fence-sitting
18. No real structure
No clear argument
19. & Bibliography
20. References in text: Authors last name, date of publication and page number (could be put in foot note)
Bibliography:
Consistent
Alphabetical order
Date order
Name of author
Date of publication
Title
Book/journal title (issue)
Publisher
21.
Incomplete references
Lacking page numbers
Lacking date/author
Bibliography lacking information
Wikipedia reference
This will lose marks!
22. No referencing
No bibliography
Say goodbye to 10 marks from your essay
2.1 becomes a 2.2!
23. When considering Frankfurt style cases we need to be careful to remember what they do and do not show: As Kadri Vihvelin says, what they do not show is that abilities to do otherwise are irrelevant to human action (Vihvelin 2005, pp.31-32). In fact, it should be clear that Frankfurt cases fail to show that alternate possibilities are necessary for human action and that we should adopt a system which provides a compatibilist understanding of ‘ability to do otherwise.’
If alternate possibilities were not necessary for freedom then we would be right to adopt a determinist position; however, seeing as Vihvelin has shown that they are in fact necessary, we should reject the determinist position in favour of a Libertarian metaphysics.
24. In this section I make the following two claims: (i) Taking responsibility is not a necessary condition on having control over an actions performance; and (ii) having control over an action’s performance is not sufficient for being morally responsible for that action (and its consequences).
Taking responsibility for an action, according to Fischer and Ravizza, involves forming an attitude towards the kind of behaviour realised by that action such that (a) one sees oneself as the agent of that kind of behaviour; and (b) one sees oneself as an apt target for the reactive attitudes which that behaviour might generate (1998: p.225). Call this a responsibility attitude.
If we can present a case in which an agent is in control of what they are doing, and yet lacks a responsibility attitude, we will have shown that such an attitude is not a necessary condition on control (Mele 2000 makes a similar point in relation to taking responsibility being a necessary condition on moral responsibility).
25. Should we think that reasons are internal or external? It is thought by many that an answer to this question is especially important if we want to come to a firm conclusion about whether there can be an objective rational standpoint that a person can take: If reasons are internal then what is rational looks subjective; whereas if they are external they ought to be an objectively rational course of action to take.
Bernard Williams first introduced this distinction in his 1981 Moral Luck and since then it has been taken up into the general discourse of philosophers of action (most notably Kosgaard and Velleman). Now, more than ever, it looks as though we are in a position to give an answer to this question. If reasons are internal then they are reasons for an agent only if they have a relevant desire. If they are external however, they will be reasons for an agent irrespective of their set of desires. We might think that moral reasons are external seeing as it seems we have an obligation, say, not to kill irrespective of what we desire. This lends itself to the thesis that reasons are external. However, if we consider more pragmatic reasons they seem much more clearly internal. For example, we only have a reason to open a door if we desire to go through it.
26. Michael Rushmichael.rush@manchester.ac.ukChris Ovendenchris.ovenden@manchester.ac.uk
27. Q&A