1 / 13

Boyer on Euclid

Boyer on Euclid.

nigelb
Download Presentation

Boyer on Euclid

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. Boyer on Euclid There is no introduction or preamble to the work, and the first book opens abruptly with a list of twenty-three definitions. The weakness here is that some of the definitions do not define, inasmuch as there is no prior set of undefined elements in terms of which to define the others. Thus to say, as does Euclid, that "a point is that which has no part, " or that "a line is breadthless length," or that "a surface is that which has length and breadth only," is scarcely to define these entities, for a definition must be expressed in terms of things that precede, and are better known than the things defined.

  2. Boyer on Euclid Objections can easily be raised on the score of logical circularity to other so-called "definitions" of Euclid, such as "The extremities of a line are points," or "A straight line is a line which lies evenly with the points on itself’’ or “The extremities of a surface are lines’’, all of which may have been due to Plato. The Euclidean definition of a plane angle as "the inclination to one another of two lines in a plane which meet one another and do not lie in a straight line" is vitiated by the fact that "inclination" has not been previously defined and is not better known than the word "angle."

  3. Boyer on Euclid Following the definitions, Euclid lists five postulates and five common notions. Aristotle had made a sharp distinction between axioms (or common notions) and postulates; the former, he said, must be convincing in themselves - truths common to all studies - but the latter are less obvious and do not presuppose the assent of the learner, for they pertain only to the subject at hand. Some later writers distinguished between the two types of assumptions by applying the word axiom to something known or accepted as obvious, while the word postulate referred to something to be "demanded“.

  4. Boyer on Euclid We do not know whether Euclid subscribed to either of these views, or even whether he distinguished between two types of assumptions. Surviving manuscripts are not in agreement here, and in some cases the ten assumptions appear together in a single category. Modern mathematicians see no essential difference between an axiom and a postulate.

  5. Burton Detailed scrutiny for over 2000 years has revealed numerous flaws in Euclid's treatment of geometry. Most of his definitions are open to criticism on one ground or another. It is curious that while Euclid recognized the necessity for a set of statements to be assumed at the outset of the discourse, he failed to realize the necessity of undefined terms. A definition, after all, merely gives the meaning of a word in terms of other, simpler words or words whose meaning is already clear. These words are in their turn defined by even simpler words. Clearly the process of definition in a logical system cannot be continued backward without an end. The only way to avoid the completion of a vicious circle is to allow certain terms to remain undefined.

  6. Burton Euclid mistakenly tried to define the entire technical vocabulary that he used. Inevitably this led him into some curious and unsatisfactory definitions. We are told not what a point and a line are but rather what they are not: "A point is that which has no parts." "A line is without breadth." (What, then, is part or breadth?) Ideas of "point" and "line" are the most elementary notions in geometry. They can be described and explained but cannot satisfactorily be defined by concepts simpler than themselves. There must be a start somewhere in a self-contained system, so they should be accepted without rigorous definition.

  7. Burton Perhaps the greatest objection that has been raised against the author of the Elements is the woeful inadequacy of his axioms. He formally postulated some things, yet omitted any mention of others that are equally necessary for his work. Aside from the obvious failure to state that points and lines exist or that the line segment joining two points is unique, Euclid made certain tacit assumptions that were used later in the deductions but not granted by the postulates and not derivable from them. Quite a few of Euclid's proofs were based on reasoning from diagrams, and he was often misled by visual evidence. This is exemplified by the argument used in his very first proposition (more a problem than a theorem). It involved the familiar construction of an equilateral triangle on a given line segment as base.

  8. Burton There is only one problem with all this. On the basis of spatial intuition, one feels certain that the two circles will intersect at a point C and will not, somehow or other, slip through each other. Yet the purpose of an axiomatic theory is precisely to provide a system of reasoning free of the dependence on intuition. The whole proposition fails if the circles we are told to construct do not intersect, and there is unhappily nothing in Euclid's postulates that guarantees that they do. To remedy this situation, one must add a postulate that will ensure the" continuity" of lines and circles.

  9. Burton Later mathematicians satisfactorily filled the gap with the following: If a circle or line has one point outside and one point inside another circle, then it has two points in common with the circle. The mere statement of the postulate involves notions of "inside" and "outside" that do not explicitly appear in the Elements. If geometry is to fulfill its reputation for logical perfection, considerable attention must be paid to the meaning of such terms and to the axioms governing them.

  10. Burton During the last 25 years of the nineteenth century, many mathematicians attempted: to give a complete statement of the postulates needed for proving all the long-familiar theorems of Euclidean geometry. They tried, that is, to supply such additional postulates as would give explicitness and form to the ideas that Euclid left intuitive. By far the most influential treatise on geometry of modem times was the work of the renowned German mathematician David Hilbert (1862-1943). Hilbert, who worked in several areas of mathematics during a long career, published in 1899 his main geometrical work, Grundlagen der Geometrie (Foundations of Geometry). In it he rested Euclidean geometry on twenty-one postulates involving six undefined terms - with which we should contrast Euclid's five postulates and no undefined terms.

  11. Morris Kline Euclid does not naively assume that the defined concepts exist or are consistent; as Aristotle had pointed out, one might define something that had incompatible properties. The first three postulates, since they declare the possibilityof constructing liens and circles, are existence assertions for these two entities. In the development of Book I, Euclid proves the existence of the other entities by constructing them. An exception is the plane.

  12. Morris Kline Euclid presupposes that the line in Postulate 1 is unique; this assumption is implicit in Book I, Proposition 4. It would have been better, however, to make it explicit. Likewise, in Postulate 2 Euclid assumes the extension is unique. He uses the uniqueness explicitly in Book XI, Proposition 1, but has actually already used it unconsciously at the very beginning of Book I.

  13. Morris Kline Postulate 5 is Euclid’s own; it is a mark of his genius that he recognized its necessity. Many Greeks objected to this postulate because it was not clearly self-evident and hence lacked the appeal of the others. The attempts to prove it from the other axioms and postulates – which, according to Proclus, commenced even in Euclid’s own time – all failed.

More Related